nLab Cohesive Toposes and Cantor's "lauter Einsen"

Redirected from "Cohesive Toposes and Cantor's lauter Einsen".
Note: Cohesive Toposes and Cantor's "lauter Einsen" and Cohesive Toposes and Cantor's "lauter Einsen" both redirect for "Cohesive Toposes and Cantor's lauter Einsen".
Contents

Context

Foundations

foundations

The basis of it all

 Set theory

set theory

Foundational axioms

foundational axioms

Removing axioms

Duality

Philosophy

Cohesive Toposes

Contents

Summary

This page collects material related to the article

on adjoint cylinders and cohesive toposes.

Overview of the paper

The article claims that Georg Cantor‘s original use of terminology (Cantor 1895) was distorted by his editor to become what we now take to be the standard meaning of sets and their cardinality in set theory. But that instead Cantor really meant “cohesive types” when saying “Menge” and used “Kardinale” really for what we call the underlying set X\flat X of a cohesive type XX.

Beyond this, the article is in part motivated from attempts to formalize thoughts appearing in Georg Hegel‘s Science of Logic on unity of opposites.

Concretely it is about the unity of opposites that in a set all elements are “distinct, but indistinguishable”. Lawvere argues that this and Cantor’s original notion of cardinality is captured by the adjoint modality given by flat modality \dashv sharp modality.

This seems to match well with Hegel‘s Pure quantity both informally as well as formally (as discussed there).

Notice that where the English translations of Hegel‘s Science of Logic say “the One”, the original has “Das Eins”, which might just as well be translated with “The Unit”. In view of this and looking through Hegel’s piece on discreteness and repulsion, it seems clear that Hegel’s “Einsen” is precisely Cantor’s “Einsen” as recalled by Lawvere. Namely: copies of the unit type.

Notice that the German “lauter” is pretty much the English “lots of”. When you say “A lot o'” as in the slang “A lot o' stuff” or else say “lauter” with a Bavarian accent, it comes out pretty much alike.

(? The German expression ‘lauter’ predominantly denotes universal quantification, so that the Cantor quote translates ‘all (of) units’. There might in fact be an etymological connection to English ‘lot’ preserved in the meaning ‘(specific) quantity’ - German ‘Posten’ like in e.g. ‘yesterday arrived two lots of cd-players’)

On page 7, Lawvere makes a distinction between objective and subjective cohesion. The subjective version involve the “coming to know” aspects of points in a space. “A good example of a type of set possessing subjective cohesion is that of recursive set, which is ‘traced’ by various threads generated by particular recursive functions.”

In view of the relationship between cohesion and modality, Lawvere’s distinction should correspond to that between metaphysical and epistemic modalities (“As far as I know, it may be the case that…”).

On page 11, Lawvere discusses categories intermediate between the original cohesive category and the base. This relates to the discussion, pp. 10-11 of Some Thoughts on the Future of Category Theory, which remarks on dimensional levels of increasing determinateness, including infinitesimal increases.

The fortunes and misfortunes of Euclid’s units

It is noteworthy that Cantor’s conception of cardinal number is a mildly disguised form of the definition of number as ‘a multitude made up of units’ in Euclid, book VII, def.2. This was until the end of the 19th century a standard definition of the finite cardinals and in Cantor’s time was e.g. used by the highly influential Karl Weierstrass in his lectures1 and defended by Weierstrass’ student Edmund Husserl in his ‘Philosophie der Arithmetik’ (1891).

Cantor comments on Euclid in ‘Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten’ (1887-88, Cantor (1932) pp.378-438)). His comment (p.380f.) makes it clear that he views cardinals actually as the cohesive ‘united’ objects whereas he stresses the discreteness of the concrete elements in the ‘Mengen’. He criticizes Euclid for not emphasizing that numbers are actually more unified objects than the material sets they are abstracted from. Another key passage (with unmistakingly Aristotelian overtones) in this direction reads:

Die Elemente der uns gegenüberstehenden Menge MM sind getrennt vorzustellen; in dem intellektualem Gebilde M¯\overline{M}, welches ich ihren Ordnungstypus nenne, sind dagegen die Einsen zu einem Organismus vereinigt. In gewissem Sinne lässt sich jeder Ordnungstypus als ein Kompositum aus Materie und Form ansehen; die darin enthaltenen begrifflich unterschiedenen Einsen liefern die Materie, während die unter diese bestehende Ordnung das der Form entsprechende ist.’ (p.380)

In a letter to Peano he writes:

I conceive of numbers as ‘forms’ or ‘species’ (general concepts) of sets. In essentials this is the conception of the ancient geometry of Plato, Aristotle, Euclid etc.’ (Cantor, Briefe, 1991, p.365; quoted after Hill (2000))

What underlies the contrast between Mengen and Kardinalen, is a platonist conception of mathematics. By abstracting from the contingencies of the material sets one reaches a realm of ideas of higher reality as they achieve a better unification of the many into unity; in particular, the introduction of the units acts as a uniformisation and homogenisation of the diversity-matter of the concrete sets which are then able to participate in the idea of the cardinal number. The pertinent contrast in Cantor is between concrete-particular vs. abstract-general. Moreover, it seems, that though cardinals are indeed (related to) ‘abstract sets’, a general concept of ‘abstract set’ is absent here, as on Cantor’s view there can only be one abstract set of a given cardinality i.e. according to Cantor there is something like THE number 2. It seems also somewhat paradoxically to come up with rudimentary structural set theory in order to do transfinite arithmetic !

The views advanced in R. Dedekind’s ‘Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?’ (1887) appear to be a more decisive step towards the modern structural approach to set theory and mathematics. Though he similarly defines the natural numbers in §6.73 by abstraction as a certain ‘simple infinite set’, he clearly has a concept of such a system up to isomorphism: he has also a more general view of ‘abstract set’ (see also the quote in the footnote at ETCS) and of the importance of mathematics ‘up to isomorphism’. Furthermore, he stresses the fundamental importance of maps between sets as basic concept in general.

The abstractionist view was severely criticized by Gottlob Frege in ‘Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik’ (1884) and his reviews of Cantor and Husserl (1892,1894). Frege rejected the process of ‘abstraction’ involved in such accounts and held views on identity that made the ‘distinct yet indistinguishable units’ an inconsistent concept and spoke therefore sarcastically of ‘unglückliche Einsen’ - ‘unfortunate units’: the adjective has stuck in this context as we find it repeated in Zermelo’s and Tait’s discussion of Cantor’s conception.

  • ncafé discussion: Rethinking Set Theory ? (link)

  • Francois Dorais : Back to Cantor ? (link)

References

Lawvere takes this interpretation of Cantor up again in

  • F. William Lawvere, Foundations and Applications: Axiomatization and Education, Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 9 no.2 (2003) pp.213-224. (ps-preprint)

He gives prominence to the essentiality of the double negation topos and the “Cantor comonad” that comes with it in the more recent

  • F. William Lawvere, Birkhoff’s theorem from a geometric

    perspective: A simple example_ , Categories and General Algebraic Structures with Applications 4 no.1 (2015) pp.1–7. (pdf)

Judging from the preface to (Lawvere-Rosebrugh 2003) Myhill made his observation presumably in Lawvere’s 1985 course. C. McLarty interprets Cantor’s cardinals as abstract sets in a well-pointed topos in

The Cantor text Lawvere refers to is

The text is reprinted on pp.282-351 of Cantor’s collected works and the revelant comment by Zermelo is in the second annotation on p.351:

  • Ernst Zermelo (ed.), Georg Cantor - Gesammelte Abhandlungen Mathematischen und Philosophischen Inhalts , Springer Berlin 1932. (gdz)

An English version of Cantor’s 1885 review of Frege appears as

  • P. A. Ebert, M. Rossberg, Cantor on Frege’s Foundations of Arthmetic , Hist. Phil. Logic 30 no.4 (2010) pp.341-348. (draft)

For an extensive discussion and relevant quotes of Cantor’s platonism and abstractionism see

  • C. O. Hill, Abstraction and Idealization in Edmund Husserl and Georg Cantor prior to 1895 , in Hill, Haddock (eds.), Husserl or Frege, Meaning, Objectivity and Mathematics , Open Court Chicago 2000.

For a recent controversial discussion of Cantorian abstraction, the second article using MLTT:

  • K. Fine, Cantorian abstraction: A reconstruction and defense , J. Phil. 95 no.12 (1998) pp.599-634.

  • W. Hinzen, Constructive versus Ontological Construals of Cantorian Ordinals , Hist. Phil. Logic 24 no.1 (2003) pp.45-63.

The key concepts of ‘one’ and ‘many’ taken from Plato’s ‘Philebus’ dialogue reappear in Hegel’s “set theory”:

  • Alan L. T. Paterson, Frege and Hegel on concepts and number, ms. n.d. University of Colorado Boulder. (pdf)

For more on the Frege-Cantor debate on the concept of cardinal number, which touches upon the status of structural mathematics more generally, see

  • William W. Tait, Frege versus Cantor and Dedekind: On the Concept of Number , pp.213-248 in Tait (ed.), Frege, Russell, Wittgenstein: Essays in Early Analytic Philosophy , Lasalle Open Court Press 1996. (preprint)

For a proposal that contrasts Cantorian set theory with Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory (though leaving out the question of abstract sets) see

  • J. Lake, The Approaches to Set Theory , Notre Dame J. Formal Logic 20 no.2 (1979) pp.415-437. (pdf)
category: reference

  1. It seems somewhat ironical that Weierstrass whose quest for arithmetical foundations of analysis was one of the main driving forces behind 19th mathematics’ move towards set-theoretic foundations actually held views on his fundamental concept ‘number’ that are closely related to a structural view!

Last revised on October 12, 2021 at 07:36:16. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.