nLab double negation translation

Contents

Contents

Idea

Double negation translation is a method for converting propositions valid in classical logic into propositions valid in intuitionistic logic. It can be used to establish relative consistency results. For example, it may be possible to show that the proof of a contradiction in a classical theory could be translated to the proof of a contradiction in a constructive theory. Kurt Gödel used this technique to show that Peano arithmetic and Heyting arithmetic are equiconsistent.

Double negation translation was discovered independently by a number of mathematicians including Kurt Gödel, Gerhard Gentzen, and Andrey Kolmogorov, and is also called the Gödel–Gentzen negative translation.

Construction

The traditional descriptions are highly syntactic, but can be motivated by recalling some conceptual relationships between Boolean algebras (which are algebras for classical propositional logic) and Heyting algebras (which are algebras for intuitionistic propositional logic).

Propositional case

Recall from the article Heyting algebra that the left adjoint FF to the forgetful functor

U:BoolHeytU \colon Bool \to Heyt

is given objectwise by taking a Heyting algebra LL to the poset L ¬¬L_{\neg\neg} of regular elements xLx \in L, i.e., those that are fixed by double negation: x=¬¬xx = \neg \neg x. It was shown that L ¬¬L_{\neg\neg} is a Boolean algebra, and ¬¬:LL ¬¬\neg \neg \colon L \to L_{\neg\neg} is a Heyting algebra homomorphism which is universal among Heyting algebra maps LUBL \to U B into Boolean algebras.

In particular, if Heyt(S)Heyt(S) is the free Heyting algebra on a set of variables SS, it follows by composing left adjoints

SetfreeHeytFBoolSet \stackrel{free}{\to} Heyt \stackrel{F}{\to} Bool

that Heyt(S) ¬¬Heyt(S)_{\neg\neg} is the free Boolean algebra on SS.

Furthermore, it was shown in Heyting algebra that for Heyting algebras LL,

  • ¬¬:LL\neg\neg \colon L \to L preserves finite meets;

  • ¬¬:LL\neg\neg \colon L \to L preserves the implication operation \Rightarrow.

Consequently, the inclusion of regular elements L ¬¬LL_{\neg\neg} \to L also preserves meets and implications, strictly. This gives the following result.

Glivenko’s Theorem

If pqp \Rightarrow q is a tautology in classical propositional logic, then (¬¬p)(¬¬q)(\neg \neg p) \Rightarrow (\neg \neg q) is a tautology in intuitionistic propositional logic, and conversely.

Proof

Here pp and qq are term expressions in variables x iSx_i \in S over the signature (0,1,,,)(0, 1, \vee, \wedge, \Rightarrow). To say pqp \Rightarrow q is a classical tautology means that 1(pq)1 \leq (p \Rightarrow q) holds when interpreted in Bool(S)Bool(S). But since Bool(S)=Heyt(S) ¬¬Bool(S) = Heyt(S)_{\neg\neg}, this is equivalent to saying that

1¬¬(pq)=(¬¬p)(¬¬q)1 \leq \neg\neg(p \Rightarrow q) = (\neg\neg p) \Rightarrow (\neg\neg q)

when interpreted in Heyt(S)Heyt(S), which is to say that (¬¬p)(¬¬q)(\neg \neg p) \Rightarrow (\neg\neg q) is an intuitionistic tautology.

Continuing this thought: the join \vee in Bool(S)=Heyt ¬¬Bool(S) = Heyt_{\neg\neg} is computed as

a Boolb=¬¬(a Heytb)a \vee_{Bool} b = \neg\neg(a \vee_{Heyt} b)

since ¬¬:Heyt(S)Heyt(S) ¬¬\neg\neg \colon Heyt(S) \to Heyt(S)_{\neg\neg} preserves joins (it is a left adjoint). Putting all this together, because ¬¬:Heyt(S)Heyt(S) ¬¬\neg\neg \colon Heyt(S) \to Heyt(S)_{\neg\neg} preserves Heyting algebra structure, we arrive at the following syntactic translation.

Definition

The double-negation translation pp Np \mapsto p^{N} on term expressions in the theory of Heyting algebras LL is defined by induction as follows.

  • x N=¬¬xx^N = \neg\neg x for variables xx.

  • 0 N=00^N = 0 (since ¬¬:LL\neg\neg \colon L \to L preserves 00)

  • 1 N=11^N = 1 (since ¬¬:LL\neg\neg \colon L \to L preserves 11)

  • (pq) N=p Nq N(p \wedge q)^N = p^N \wedge q^N (since ¬¬:LL\neg\neg \colon L \to L preserves the meet operation)

  • (pq) N=p Nq N(p \Rightarrow q)^N = p^N \Rightarrow q^N (since ¬¬:LL\neg\neg \colon L \to L preserves the implication operation)

  • (pq) N=¬¬(p Nq N)(p \vee q)^N = \neg\neg(p^N \vee q^N).

Thus, by Glivenko’s theorem, pp is a classical tautology if and only if p Np^N is an intuitionistic tautology. This result may be extended to theories as well: suppose LL is an intuitionistic theory or Heyting algebra, given by a presentation as a coequalizer in HeytHeyt:

Heyt(T)Heyt(S)L.Heyt(T) \stackrel{\to}{\to} Heyt(S) \to L.

Then, since the functor LL ¬¬L \mapsto L_{\neg\neg} is a left adjoint, it takes this coequalizer to a coequalizer

Bool(T)Bool(S)L ¬¬Bool(T) \stackrel{\to}{\to} Bool(S) \to L_{\neg\neg}

so that an term expression pp is a theorem in the classical theory L ¬¬L_{\neg\neg} if and only if p Np^N is a theorem in the intuitionistic theory LL.

First-order case

Double negation translation for a formula, ϕ\phi, of a first-order language is defined inductively by the following clauses:

  • ϕ N=¬¬ϕ\phi^N = \neg \neg \phi, for atomic ϕ\phi.

  • (ϕψ) N=ϕ Nψ N(\phi \wedge \psi)^N = \phi^N \wedge \psi^N.

  • (ϕψ) N=¬(¬ϕ N¬ψ N)(\phi \vee \psi)^N = \neg(\neg \phi^N \wedge \neg \psi^N) (or equivalently, ¬¬(ϕ Nψ N)\neg \neg (\phi^N \vee \psi^N))

  • (ϕψ) N=ϕ Nψ N(\phi \to \psi)^N = \phi^N \to \psi^N.

  • (¬ϕ) N=¬ϕ N(\neg \phi)^N = \neg \phi^N.

  • (xϕ) N=xϕ N(\forall x \phi)^N = \forall x \phi^N.

  • (xϕ) N=¬x¬ϕ N(\exists x \phi)^N = \neg \forall x \neg \phi^N (or equivalently, ¬¬xϕ N\neg \neg \exists x \phi^N).

Higher-order case

The basic idea here is that any topos EE gives rise to a Boolean topos E ¬¬E_{\neg\neg}.

References

Informal exposition of a tiny aspect of this double negation business is in

Last revised on May 10, 2017 at 08:09:12. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.