nLab 2-category equipped with proarrows

Redirected from "equipment".
Contents

Contents

Idea

A 2-category equipped with proarrows, also called a proarrow equipment or simply an equipment, is a 2-category together with extra “proarrows” which enable one to reproduce more category theory inside it than is possible in a general 2-category. The ur-example is Cat equipped with profunctors.

See also framed bicategory.

Motivation

Just as ordinary category theory provides a framework in which one can do “formal mathematics,” one of the (many) purposes of higher category theory is to provide a framework in which one can do formal category theory. In particular, many concepts in ordinary category theory can be interpreted internally in a 2-category, in a way which specializes to the original concept in Cat. Examples of such concepts include adjunctions, monads, Grothendieck fibrations, Kan extensions, and fully faithful morphisms.

However, these internalizations are not always “correct” in every 2-category. For instance, in the 2-category VCatV Cat of categories enriched in a monoidal category VV, internal adjunctions and monads give the correct notion of VV-adjunction and VV-monad, but internal fully-faithfulness for a VV-functor is weaker than the “correct” notion of VV-fully-faithfulness. More technically, in many cases the naive notion of Kan extension is not sufficient and one needs “pointwise” Kan extensions; with some more work these can also be defined in a 2-category, but the resulting notion (though correct in CatCat) is not always correct in VCatV Cat.

Furthermore, some concepts of category theory are difficult to interpret at all in a 2-category. The notion of limit in ordinary category theory can be interpreted in a 2-category by identifying the limit of a functor DCD\to C as its Kan extension along the unique functor D*D\to *. However, in enriched category theory the more important notion is that of weighted limit, and there is no straightforward way to interpret this in VCatV Cat.

What is missing is that the 2-category VCatV Cat doesn’t natively supply any information about the VV-valued hom-functors in a 2-category. (In CatCat these hom-functors can be recovered by looking at comma categories, which can be interpreted internally as comma objects—in some sense this is what all the above internalizations are secretly doing.) Thus, all of these problems can be remedied by equipping a 2-category with extra structure which describes these hom-functors, or more generally describes a notion of profunctor.

There are several not-quite-equivalent ways to describe this extra structure. One due to Street and Walters, called a Yoneda structure, involves assigning to each object AA a “presheaf object” PAP A and a “Yoneda arrow” APAA\to P A; a profunctor ABA\to B is then identified with an arrow BPAB \to P A. The notion of proarrow equipment, due to Wood, instead postulates an additional bicategory of “proarrows” and specifies their relationship to the ordinary arrows. One can then define fully faithful morphisms, pointwise Kan extensions, weighted limits, etc. relative to this structure, in a way which specializes to the correct notions in VCatV Cat.

Definitions

There are several equivalent ways to define proarrow equipments on a 2-category.

Definition as a 2-functor

Let KK be a 2-category. The following structure is said to equip KK with proarrows.

  • A 2-category MM, whose arrows are called proarrows.
  • A functor KMK\to M which is bijective on objects and locally fully faithful. If f:ABf\colon A\to B is a 1-morphism in KK, we write its image in MM as B(1,f):ABB(1,f)\colon A\nrightarrow B.
  • For each arrow f:ABf\colon A\to B in KK, the proarrow B(1,f):ABB(1,f)\colon A\to B has a right adjoint in MM, which we write as B(f,1)B(f,1).

As usual on the nLab, here by 2-category we mean a weak 2-category (aka bicategory) and by functor we mean a weak 2-functor (aka pseudofunctor). However, in many or most examples, KK is in fact a strict 2-category.

For a proarrow H:BDH\colon B\to D and ordinary arrows f:ABf\colon A\to B and g:CDg\colon C\to D, we write H(g,f)H(g,f) for the composite D(g,1)HB(1,f)D(g,1) \circ H \circ B(1,f); it is a proarrow from AA to CC. We also write U AU_A, A(1,1)A(1,1), or simply AA for the identity proarrow AAA\nrightarrow A.

Note that in the case where proarrows are profunctors, H(g,f)H(g, f) is not the action on a set of heteromorphisms by pre- and post- composing with morphisms; instead it is the functor ff, followed by the profunctor HH, followed by taking the preimage under the functor gg, resulting in a profunctor from AA to CC.

Terminology

We refer to the entire structure defined above as a 2-category equipped with proarrows or a 2-category proarrow equipment. Those working in the field often use the term proarrow equipment or simply equipment for the entire structure. We prefer “2-category equipped with proarrows” (or, equivalently, “pro-morphisms”) for the following reasons:

  • It conveys that we are talking about extra stuff added to a 2-category. (Actually, it is “eka-stuff” or “2-stuff” in the sense of stuff, structure, property.)
  • It includes the word “proarrow” which tells people what the extra stuff consists of, namely a generalization of profunctors.
  • It includes the word “equipment” which signals what is meant to readers who are familiar with that term.

We do sometimes avail ourselves of the shorter terminology “proarrow equipment,” however, once we are clear what is under discussion.

Examples

For example, if VV is a (Benabou) cosmos, the 2-category K=VCatK= V Cat of VV-enriched categories is equipped with proarrows by the 2-category M=VModM=V Mod of VV-enriched profunctors, where B(1,f)B(1,f) and B(f,1)B(f,1) are the two ways of regarding a VV-functor f:ABf:A\to B as a profunctor, namely B(,f)B(-,f-) and B(f,)B(f-,-) (hence the notation in the general case). Composition of VV-profunctors is by tensor product, i.e. coends; note that we require VV to be cocomplete with colimits preserved by \otimes on both sides in order to form such associative tensor products. In VCatV Cat, H(g,f)H(g,f) is the result of precomposing the profunctor H:D opBVH:D^{op}\otimes B \to V with g opfg^{op}\otimes f.

The other most common sorts of generalized category, such as internal categories in some category with pullbacks, and fibered categories over some base, are also naturally equipped with proarrows. For internal categories in SS, we require SS to have finite limits and coequalizers preserved by pullback in order for the bicategory of internal profunctors to have associative compositions. (See “virtual equipments,” below, for a context which avoids some of these restrictions on VV and SS.)

Definition as a double category

We discuss now how a 2-category with proarrow equipment is equivalently a double category with extra structure.

Given a 2-category KK equipped with proarrows, we can construct a double category having the same objects as KK, whose vertical 1-cells are the arrows, whose horizontal 1-cells are the proarrows, and whose squares

A H C f g B J D\array{A & \overset{H}{\to} & C \\ ^f\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^g\\ B& \underset{J}{\to} & D}

are the 2-cells HJ(g,f)H \to J(g,f). Note that if KK is a strict 2-category, then this is a pseudo double category (vertically strict and horizontally weak) while if KK and MM are both weak 2-categories, this double category is weak in both directions (like a double bicategory).

In VCatV Cat, for example, the squares of the above form are transformations H(b,a)J(gb,fa)H(b,a) \to J(g b,f a) natural in aa and bb. Arguably, this double category is a more fundamental and natural object than the 2-functor VCatVProfV Cat \to V Prof. More generally, if KK is any 2-category equipped with proarrows, we can reconstruct KK and its proarrow equipment from the double category defined above, and we can characterize the double categories that arise in this way.

One way to state this characterization is that they are those in which every vertical 1-cell f:ABf\colon A\to B has both a companion (namely B(1,f)B(1,f)) and a conjoint (namely B(f,1)B(f,1)). One can then recover KK and MM as the vertical and horizontal 2-categories, respectively, and the 2-functor KMK\to M as the functor taking every vertical arrow to its companion. Whenever a vertical arrow has both a companion B(1,f)B(1,f) and a conjoint B(f,1)B(f,1), we automatically have an adjunction B(1,f)B(f,1)B(1,f)\dashv B(f,1), so this defines a proarrow equipment in the first sense.

Another, perhaps even more natural, way to characterize these double categories is as those with the following property: given any “niche”

A B f g C J D\array{A & & B\\ ^f\downarrow & & \downarrow^g\\ C& \underset{J}{\nrightarrow} & D}

there exists a “universal” or “cartesian” filler square

A J(g,f) B f g C J D \array{A & \overset{J(g,f)}{\to} & B\\ ^f\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^g\\ C& \underset{J}{\nrightarrow} & D}

with the property that any other square

X Y fh gk C J D \array{X & \nrightarrow & Y\\ ^{f h}\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^{g k}\\ C& \underset{J}{\nrightarrow} & D}

factors through the universal one uniquely:

X Y h ! k A J(g,f) B f g C J D \array{X & \nrightarrow & Y\\ ^{h}\downarrow & \exists! \Downarrow & \downarrow^{k}\\ A & \overset{J(g,f)}{\to} & B\\ ^f\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^g\\ C& \underset{J}{\nrightarrow} & D}

The profunctor J(g,f)J(g,f) will, of course, turn out to be the same one we gave that name to earlier. The proarrows B(1,f)=U B(id B,f)B(1,f)=U_B(id_B,f) and B(f,1)=U B(f,id B)B(f,1) = U_B(f,id_B) are then a special case of this construction. We show that they are a companion and conjoint of ff, respectively, as follows.

By factoring the identity square

A U A A f U f f B U B B\array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^f\downarrow & ^{U_f}\Downarrow & \downarrow^f\\ B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B}

through the universal fillers

A B(1,f) B f id B U B BandB B(f,1) A id f B U B B\array{A & \overset{B(1,f)}{\to} & B\\ ^f\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{id}\\ B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B} \qquad\text{and}\qquad \array{B & \overset{B(f,1)}{\to} & A\\ ^{id}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{f}\\ B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B}

that define B(1,f)B(1,f) and B(f,1)B(f,1), we obtain additional squares

A U A A f id B B(f,1) AandA U A A id f A B(1,f) B\array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^f\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{id}\\ B & \underset{B(f,1)}{\to} & A} \qquad\text{and}\qquad \array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^{id}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{f}\\ A & \underset{B(1,f)}{\to} & B}

such that the composites

A U A A f id B B(f,1) A id f B U B BandA U A A id f A B(1,f) B f id B U B B\array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^{f}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{id}\\ B & \overset{B(f,1)}{\to} & A\\ ^{id}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{f}\\ B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B} \qquad\text{and}\quad \array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^{id}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{f}\\ A & \underset{B(1,f)}{\to} & B\\ ^f\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{id}\\ B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B}

are both equal to U fU_f. And using the uniqueness of factorization through the universal squares, we can conclude moreover that the composites

A U A A B(1,f) A id f id A B(1,f) B U B BandB B(f,1) A U A A id f id B U B B B(f,1) A\array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A & \overset{B(1,f)}{\to} & A\\ ^{id}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{f} & \Downarrow & \downarrow^{id}\\ A & \underset{B(1,f)}{\to} & B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B} \qquad\text{and}\qquad \array{B & \overset{B(f,1)}{\to} & A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^{id}\downarrow &\Downarrow & \downarrow^{f} & \Downarrow & \downarrow^{id}\\ B & \underset{U_B}{\to} & B & \underset{B(f,1)}{\to} & A}

are equal to the identity squares of B(1,f)B(1,f) and B(f,1)B(f,1) respectively. These are the defining equations of a companion and a conjoint.

Finally, we record the following.

Central Lemma

There is a natural bijection between squares of the form

A 0 H B 0 f 1 g 1 A 1 B 1 f 2 g 2 A 2 B 2 f 3 g 3 A 3 J B 3\array{A_0 & \overset{H}{\to} & B_0\\ ^{f_1}\downarrow && \downarrow^{g_1}\\ A_1 && B_1\\ ^{f_2}\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^{g_2}\\ A_2 && B_2\\ ^{f_3}\downarrow && \downarrow^{g_3}\\ A_3 & \underset{J}{\to} & B_3 }

and squares of the form

A 1 A 1(f 1,1) A 0 H B 0 B 1(1,g 1) B 1 f 2 g 2 A 2 A 3(1,f 3) A 3 J B 3 B 3(g 3,1) B 2.\array{A_1 & \overset{A_1(f_1 ,1)}{\to} & A_0 & \overset{H}{\to} & B_0 & \overset{B_1(1,g_1)}{\to} & B_1\\ ^{f_2}\downarrow && &\Downarrow & && \downarrow^{g_2}\\ A_2 & \underset{A_3(1,f_3)}{\to} & A_3 & \underset{J}{\to} & B_3 & \underset{B_3(g_3 ,1)}{\to} & B_2.}

One way to think of this is as saying that vertical arrows can be “slid around corners” to become horizontal arrows, turning them into the “representable proarrows” B(1,f)B(1,f) or B(f,1)B(f,1) (depending on whether you slid them “backwards” or “forwards” to get around the corner). The bijection is just given by composing with the four special squares in the definition of companions and conjoints. In particular, by a Yoneda argument, for any f:ACf\colon A\to C, g:BDg\colon B\to D, and J:CDJ\colon C\nrightarrow D we have

(1)J(g,f)C(1,f)JD(g,1)J(g,f) \cong C(1,f) \odot J \odot D(g,1)

which was what we took as the the definition of J(g,f)J(g,f) with the original definition of proarrow equipment. Thus, the companions and conjoints determine the rest of the cartesian squares. Note that this is an equipment-version of Yoneda reduction.

In conclusion, we have three definitions of proarrow equipment:

  • A 2-functor which is bijective on objects, locally fully faithful, and maps every 1-morphism to one having a right adjoint.
  • A double category in which every vertical arrow has a companion and a conjoint.
  • A double category in which every niche has a cartesian filler.

While the first definition is perhaps simpler, for some purposes the second and third definitions are preferable. For instance, the definition of the 3-category of “2-categories equipped with proarrows” is much more naturally defined by viewing them as double categories. (See Dominic Verity’s thesis and Mike Shulman’s paper on framed bicategories.) It also generalizes better to situations in which not all proarrows have composites; see “virtual equipments,” below.

As a category internal to CatCat

We discuss how a 2-category with proarrow equipment is an internal category in the (2,1)-category Cat in the sense of the theory of internal (∞,1)-categories.

(…)

For the moment see at Segal space - Examples - In 1Grpd.

There are a number of variations on the notion.

Some related concepts include:

See also at Segal space, the section Examples – In 1Grpd.

Category theory in a proarrow equipment

We now give a few examples of how to do category theory internal to a proarrow equipment.

Homset definition of adjunctions

We start with this: two (vertical) arrows f:ABf\colon A\to B and g:BAg\colon B\to A are adjoint (in 𝒱(X̲)\mathcal{V}(\underline{X})) if and only if we have an isomorphism B(f,1)A(1,g)B(f,1)\cong A(1,g). Why? Well, an adjunction fgf\dashv g comes with a unit and a counit, which (expressed in X̲\underline{X}) are of the form

A U A A f B η id g A U A AandB U B B g id ε A f B U B B.\array{A & \overset{U_A}{\to} & A\\ ^f\downarrow && \downarrow\\ B & \overset{\eta}{\Leftarrow} & \downarrow^{id} \\ ^g\downarrow && \downarrow\\ A& \underset{U_A}{\to} & A} \qquad\text{and}\qquad \array{B & \overset{U_B}{\to} & B\\ \downarrow && \downarrow^g\\ ^{id}\downarrow & \overset{\varepsilon}{\Leftarrow} & A \\ \downarrow && \downarrow^f\\ B& \underset{U_B}{\to} & B.}

Applying the bijection of the Central Lemma, we see that η\eta corresponds to a map B(f,1)A(1,g)B(f,1) \to A(1,g), and likewise ε\varepsilon corresponds to a map A(1,g)B(f,1)A(1,g)\to B(f,1). The triangle identities for η\eta and ε\varepsilon are then equivalent to saying that these two maps are inverse isomorphisms. So we’ve recovered the classical equivalence between the “diagrammatic” and isomorphism-of-hom-sets definitions of an adjunction, in a purely formal way.

Fully faithful arrows

An arrow f:ABf:A\to B in a 2-category equipped with proarrows is said to be fully faithful if the canonical morphism U AB(f,f)U_A\to B(f,f) is an isomorphism of proarrows AAA\to A. In VCatV Cat this recaptures the correct notion of VV-fully-faithful VV-functor.

It is not hard to see, using the fact that KMK\to M is locally fully faithful, that any fully-faithful arrow f:ABf\colon A\to B is, in fact, internally fully-faithful in KK in the sense that K(X,A)K(X,B)K(X,A)\to K(X,B) is fully faithful for all XKX\in K. However, the converse fails in general. But it is not hard to show that the two are equivalent if f:ABf\colon A\to B has a left or right adjoint, using the above characterization of adjunctions.

Limits

The notion of limit we end up in a 2-category equipped with proarrows with is actually more general than what you’re probably used to, but this extra generality turns out to be useful. Let d:DCd\colon D\to C be an arrow and let J:DAJ\colon D\nrightarrow A be a proarrow; we’re going to define what it means for an arrow :AC\ell\colon A\to C to be the JJ-weighted limit of dd. In the proarrow-equipped 2-category VCatV Cat of VV-enriched categories, if AA is the unit VV-category II, then this will recover the usual notion of weighted limit. Of course, in a general proarrow equipment we may not have a “unit object,” so that extra generality is unavoidable; it’s like using generalized elements in ordinary category theory.

To make things easier, let’s assume that our proarrow equipment is closed, in the sense that composition of proarrows has adjoints in each variable

(X̲)(HK,L)(X̲)(H,KL)(X̲)(K,LH). \mathcal{H}(\underline{X})(H\odot K,L) \cong \mathcal{H}(\underline{X})(H,K\rhd L) \cong \mathcal{H}(\underline{X})(K,L\lhd H).

The Central Lemma implies that analogously to (1), we have

(2)K(g,f)D(1,g)KC(f,1).K(g,f) \cong D(1,g)\rhd K \lhd C(f,1).

In V-ProfV\text{-}Prof, the adjoints are given by the ends

(KL)(b,a)= cC[K(c,b),L(c,a)] (K\rhd L)(b,a) = \int_{c\in C} [K(c,b), L(c,a)]

and

(LH)(c,b)= aA[H(b,a),L(c,a)]. (L \lhd H)(c,b) = \int_{a\in A} [H(b,a), L(c,a)].

Therefore, (2) is an abstract form of the Yoneda lemma, just as (1) is an abstract form of Yoneda reduction.

Now recall that for VV-categories DD and CC, an object C\ell\in C is a JJ-weighted limit of d:DCd\colon D\to C if we have a natural isomorphism

C(c,) [D,V](J,C(c,d())) = xD[J(x),C(c,d(x))]. \begin{aligned} C(c,\ell) &\cong [D,V](J, C(c,d(-)))\\ &= \int_{x\in D} [J(x), C(c,d(x))]. \end{aligned}

Thus it makes sense to define, in a closed proarrow equipment, an arrow :AC\ell\colon A\to C to be the JJ-weighted limit of dd if we have an isomorphism

C(1,)C(1,d)J. C(1,\ell) \cong C(1,d) \lhd J.

(If our proarrow equipment is not closed, we simply assert that C(1,)C(1,\ell) has the universal property that C(1,d)JC(1,d) \lhd J would have if it existed. In other terminology, we assert that C(1,)C(1,\ell) is a right lifting of C(1,d)C(1,d) along JJ in the 2-category of proarrows.) In particular, when AA is the unit VV-category, this recovers the classical notion. But even in VCatV Cat there are interesting examples for other values of AA. If we take J=D(j,1)J = D(j,1) for some functor j:ADj\colon A\to D, then (1) and (2) imply that

C(1,d)J =C(1,d)D(j,1) j *C(1,d) D(1,j)C(1,d) C(1,dj) \begin{aligned} C(1,d) \lhd J &= C(1,d) \lhd D(j,1)\\ & \cong j^* C(1,d)\\ & \cong D(1,j) \odot C(1,d)\\ & \cong C(1,d j) \end{aligned}

so that =dj\ell = d j is the JJ-weighted limit of dd. That is, D(j,1)D(j,1)-weighted limits are just given by composition with jj.

More interestingly, one can show that if J=D(1,k)J = D(1,k) for some k:DAk\colon D\to A, then JJ-weighted limits specialize to pointwise right Kan extensions along kk. That is, the extra data of a proarrow equipment lets us define the good notion of Kan extension (even in the enriched case) as a special case of a general notion of limit. Thus, in a general 2-category equipped with proarrows, we define a “pointwise right Kan extension” along an arrow k:DAk\colon D\to A to be a D(1,k)D(1,k)-weighted limit. It is easy to show that any pointwise Kan extension is, in particular, an internal Kan extension in KK, but as we have seen the converse fails in VCatV Cat.

Right adjoints preserve limits

Suppose that :AC\ell\colon A\to C is a JJ-weighted limit of d:DCd\colon D\to C in the above sense, and let g:CBg\colon C\to B be an arrow with a left adjoint f:BCf\colon B\to C. We want to show that gg\ell is a JJ-weighted limit of gdg d. But we have

B(1,g) C(1,)B(1,g) (C(1,d)J)C(f,1) C(1,f)(C(1,d)J) (C(1,f)C(1,d))J (C(1,d)C(f,1))J (C(1,d)B(1,g))J B(1,gd)J. \begin{aligned} B(1,g\ell) &\cong C(1,\ell) \odot B(1,g)\\ &\cong \big(C(1,d) \lhd J\big) \odot C(f,1)\\ &\cong C(1,f) \rhd \big(C(1,d) \lhd J\big)\\ &\cong \big(C(1,f) \rhd C(1,d)\big) \lhd J\\ &\cong \big(C(1,d) \odot C(f,1)\big) \lhd J\\ &\cong \big(C(1,d) \odot B(1,g)\big) \lhd J\\ &\cong B(1,g d) \lhd J. \end{aligned}

which is what we want.

Graphs and cographs

As noted above, in the case of ordinary categories, the profunctors can in fact be recovered from the 2-category CatCat. Specifically, profunctors ABA\to B can be identified with two-sided discrete fibrations from BB to AA (that is, spans BCAB \leftarrow C \to A such that CBC \to B is a (Grothendieck) fibration, CAC\to A is an opfibration, the two structures are compatible, and each fiber of CB×AC\to B\times A is discrete). The two-sided fibration corresponding to a profunctor is also called its graph. The same is true for internal categories, but not for enriched categories.

However the VV-profunctors ABA\to B can be recovered from the 2-category VCatV Cat in a different, and in fact dual, way: they are the two-sided codiscrete cofibrations from BB to AA, i.e. two-sided discrete fibrations in (VCat) op(V Cat)^{op}. The two-sided cofibration corresponding to a profunctor is, unsurprisingly, its cograph, and also its collage. This was first noticed by Street and subsequently expanded on by other authors. In particular, one can write down axioms on a 2-category guaranteeing that its codiscrete cofibrations can be used to equip it with proarrows, and axioms on a proarrow equipment guaranteeing that it arises from codiscrete cofibrations.

Virtual equipments

One can formulate a generalized notion of equipment which includes VCatV Cat for any monoidal category VV (and in fact, any multicategory), and Cat(S)Cat(S) for any category SS with pullbacks. The precise definition is complicated, but the basic idea is not: we start from the double-category definition, and instead of composites of the horizontal (pro)arrows, we allow the squares to have domains that are arbitrary composable strings, like so:

.\array{ & \to \to \dots \to &\\ \downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow\\ & \underset{}{\to}& .}

So far this is analogous to the generalization from monoidal categories to multicategories, and gives the notion of virtual double category. We then impose a condition analogous to the existence of companions and conjoints to obtain the notion of virtual equipment. Most of category theory can be done in a virtual equipment just as well as in an equipment.

Categories enriched in an equipment

For any equipment WW one can define a notion of WW-enriched category. (See also at category enriched in a bicategory.) This consists of

  • a collection ob(C)ob(C) of objects,
  • for each object xx an extent e(x)e(x) which is an object of WW,
  • for each pair of objects x,yx,y a proarrow hom C(x,y):e(x)e(y)hom_C(x,y):e(x)\to e(y),
  • composition and identity-assigning 2-cells obeying associativity and unit axioms.

So far we have not used the ordinary arrows, so many authors have studied only the notion of “category enriched in a bicategory.” (Note that any 2-category MM can be regarded as the proarrow 2-category of an equipment in which the only ordinary arrows are identites.) However, we need the extra structure when we define a functor f:CDf:C\to D between WW-enriched categories, which consists of:

  • a function f:ob(C)ob(D)f:ob(C)\to ob(D),
  • for each object xx of CC an arrow f x:e(x)e(f(x))f_x:e(x)\to e(f(x)) in WW,
  • for each pair of objects xx and yy, a square
    e(y) hom C(x,y) e(x) f y f x e(f(y)) hom D(f(x),f(y)) e(f(x))\array{e(y) & \overset{hom_C(x,y)}{\to} & e(x)\\ ^{f_y}\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^{f_x}\\ e(f(y))& \underset{hom_D(f(x),f(y))}{\to} & e(f(x))}
  • satisfying functoriality axioms.

Finally, we define a natural transformation between such functors f,g:CDf,g:C\to D to consist of

  • squares
    e(x) U e(x) e(x) g x f x e(g(x)) hom D(f(x),f(y)) e(f(x))\array{e(x) & \overset{U_{e(x)}}{\to} & e(x)\\ ^{g_x}\downarrow & \Downarrow & \downarrow^{f_x}\\ e(g(x))& \underset{hom_D(f(x),f(y))}{\to} & e(f(x))}
  • satisfying a naturality axiom.

By choosing WW appropriately, categories enriched in an equipment include most types of generalized category:

  • If WW is a monoidal category VV, regarded as a one-object bicategory and thence as an equipment with only one ordinary arrow (so the objects of VV are the proarrows of WW), then WW-enriched categories, functors, and natural transformations are the same as VV-enriched ones.

  • If SS has pullbacks, there is an equipment Span(S)Span(S) whose objects and arrows are those of SS and whose proarrows are spans. A category enriched in Span(S)Span(S) which has one object is the same as an internal category in SS, and likewise for functors and transformations. (Here it is essential to use an equipment, rather than merely a bicategory, to get the right notion of functor.)

  • Arbitrary Span(S)Span(S)-enriched categories can be identified with “locally small fibrations” over SS, aka “locally internal categories” over SS.

Other choices of WW give “categories which are both enriched and internal,” for example:

  • For a suitably nice category SS (such as a Grothendieck topos) there is an equipment Ab(S)Ab(S) whose objects and arrows are those of SS, and whose proarrows ABA\to B are internal abelian group objects in S/(B×A)S/(B\times A). An Ab(S)Ab(S)-enriched category with one object can be regarded as an “internal Ab-enriched category” in SS.

References

and “Proarrows II” (the original definitions), and a number of following papers.

  • Ross Street, “Fibrations in bicategories” (Construction of VModV Mod from VCatV Cat.)

  • Aurelio Carboni, Scott Johnson, Ross Street, and Dominic Verity, “Modulated bicategories” (Improved construction of VModV Mod from VCatV Cat.)

  • Dominic Verity, “Enriched categories, internal categories, and change of base”, Ph.D. Thesis. (The connection with double categories.)

  • Michael Shulman, “Framed bicategories and monoidal fibrations”. (The equivalence with certain double categories, there called framed bicategories, and a general way to construct equipments such as Ab(S)Ab(S).)

  • Geoff Cruttwell, Michael Shulman, “A unified framework for generalized multicategories” (currently the only reference for virtual equipments).

  • Renato Betti, Aurelio Carboni, Ross Street, and Robert Walters, “Variation through enrichment.” (Locally small fibrations as SpanSpan-enriched categories.)

A blog post surveying ideas of proarrow equipments, much of which has been copied over to this page:

On a string diagram-calculus for (virtual) double categories with (virtual) pro-arrow equipments:

An (∞,1)-category theoretic version of proarrow equipments is in

Last revised on January 30, 2024 at 16:22:13. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.