David Roberts ideas

Here I list some ideas I am slowly pursuing, sometimes in collaboration with others. new link

The Lie fundamental bigroupoid of a finite dimensional manifold

Joint work with Andrew Stacey.

Outline: In my thesis I define a topological fundamental bigroupoid of a (locally well-behaved) topological space. Since the fundamental groupoid of a fin. dim. manifold can be made into a Lie groupoid, a natural idea is to form the joint generalisation of these ideas. For a description of the fundamental bigroupoid see topological fundamental bigroupoid.

One issue is this: which smooth paths do I use? One obvious solution is piecewise smooth, but Andrew tells me they do not form a nice space. The other obvious solution is paths with sitting instants, but then some of the approaches in the topological case will need some new tricks to make them work. Above all, the ‘obvious’ operations on paths (e.g. concatenation) should all be smooth.

The other things to do are: the manifold of 2-arrows and smoothness of structure maps - source-target-compositions? and smoothness of structure maps - associator-etc?.

Localizing a class of arrows to equivalences

Given a small category CC and a class of arrows WW, there is a a small category C[W 1]C[W^{-1}] and a universal functor q:CC[W 1]q:C \to C[W^{-1}] such that qq sends arrows in WW to isomorphisms. This is just from Gabriel-Zisman’s Calculus of fractions and homotopy theory.

Given a bicategory BB and a class of 1-arrows WW admitting a bicategory of fractions, we have the analogous situation for bicategories, where elements of WW are sent to equivalences.

But what about taking a small category CC and localizing it at a class of arrows WW to a bicategory, such that those arrows in the class are sent to equivalences in the bicategory, and this construction is universal in the appropriate way?

Well, every small category is a bicategory in a trivial way, so the previous construction should work, and it should result in a (2,1)(2,1)-category (a locally groupoidal bicategory). Did you want something more? —Toby

Ah, but the localisation of a general bicategory at a general class of 1-arrows has never been constructed. Pronk's axioms for fractions hold for a 1-category precisely if Gabriel-Zisman's do, and that is too strong. I was thinking more along the lines of: the localisation has as 1-arrows the paths in such-and-such a graph, and 2-arrows just enough to enforce the axioms of a bicat, weakly invertible arrows that should be, and functoriality of the inclusion of the original category. -David

You mean that Pronk\'s requirements for WW to admit a bicategory of fractions are only satisfied (when CC is a 11-category) when the resulting C[W 1]C[W^{-1}] is again a 11-category (at least up to equivalence)?

On a related note, is Pronk\'s paper (or at least a precise statement of the theorem, including the requirements on WW) available online anywhere? I can\'t find it, and getting to a library is inconvenient for me, so I haven\'t been able to check them for myself. —Toby

Here is Pronk's paper. -Mathieu

A 1-category CC satisfies the axioms for a bicategory of fractions if and only if it satisfies the axioms for a category of fractions. (This is Remark 17 in Pronk's paper, which you will have probably already seen) I haven't run through section 2.3 where she constructs the 2-cells and applied it to the case when we start with a 1-category. One reason why I like anafunctors now is that they do away with the messy '2-cells as equivalence classes of pasting diagrams' treatment. —David

Thanks, Mathieu. I\'ve looked at it before, but now I\'ll look at it again and then say something intelligent. —Toby

Given a 1-category CC, the functor CC GZC \to C_GZ (Gabriel-Zisman localization) satisfies EF1 and EF2 of proposition 24 in Pronk's article, but not necessarily EF3. But, as Matthieu pointed out in a comment

here

, this doesn't mean that C GZC_GZ is not equivalent to C PC_P (Pronk localization) in general.

(Deleted some of my own stupid comments) —David

Since C PC_P is in this case a (2,1)-category, to show it is equivalent to a 1-category all we need to do is show that the automorphism group of a given 1-cell is trivial. Using section 2.3 of Pronk's article, if

( w , f ) : A M B (w,f):A \leftarrow M \to B

is a 1-cell is C PC_P, and MNMM \leftarrow N \to M is a representative for a 2-cell from (w,f)(w,f) to itself, it is equivalent to the identity 2-cell, represented by M=M=MM \stackrel{=}{\leftarrow} M \stackrel{=}{\to} M. Hence C PC_P is (equivalent to) a 1-category.

—David

OK, I understand now, having reread Pronk and also seen the discussion at

category of fractions

. You can probably remove my remarks here. —Toby

Clearly the 1-arrows of the 2-localization C//WC//W will be finite length zig-zags where the backward pointing arrows are in WW. The trick is to introduce the minimal number of 2-arrows so that we get

  1. a pseudofunctor q:CC//Wq:C \to C//W with its coherence data
  2. invertible 2-arrows expressing the fact q(w)q(w) is an equivalence
  3. universal properties

One idea is to try the 2-localization so that the result is a (2,1)-category, i.e. all 2-arrows are invertible. The associated 1-category given by sending the hom-groupoids to their connected components will then be the ordinary localization of CC.

Last revised on April 28, 2010 at 06:40:54. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.