nLab irreducible ideal

Irreducible ideals

Irreducible ideals

Idea

Irreducible ideals generalize prime ideals by replacing multiplication? of ideals with intersection. (Strictly speaking, this gives us the notion of strongly irreducible ideals; the irreducible ideals are found by replacing a containment with an equality. However, in many common situations, these are equivalent.)

In lattices (or prosets more broadly), where multiplication of ideals is intersection, the (strongly) irreducible ideals are the same as the prime ideals; this is true in some other cases, such as the ring of integers. (For this reason, the term ‘strongly irreducible’ is not needed in order theory.)

There is also an infinitary version, the completely irreducible ideals, which also have a strong version. (The completely strongly irreducible ideals are usually called ‘completely prime’ in order theory, although they are different from the completely prime ideals of noncommutative ring theory).

Irreducible ideals are related to irreducible elements but don't line up perfectly.

Definitions

Let RR be a ring, or more generally a rig, possibly even nonassociative, or even just a monoid, possibly just a magma; or on the other hand a lattice, or even just a proset. In other words, anything with a concept of ideals. In the noncommutative case, we could be talking about left ideals, right ideals, or two-sided ideals; pick a meaning and stick with it. We need the concept of intersection of ideals (which all of these have), and that's pretty much it; that is, we use the structure of the meet-semilattice Idl(R)Idl(R) of ideals of RR.

Definition

An ideal II of RR is irreducible if II is proper and, whenever II equals the intersection of two ideals of RR, II equals at least one of those two ideals:

JIdl(R),KIdl(R),I=JKI=JI=K. \forall\, J \in Idl(R),\; \forall\, K \in Idl(R),\; I = J \cap K \;\Rightarrow\; I = J \;\vee\; I = K .

Also, II is completely irreducible if, whenever II equals the intersection of any collection of ideals of RR, II equals at least one of the ideals in that collection:

𝒥Idl(R),I=𝒥JIdl(R),J𝒥I=J. \forall\, \mathcal{J} \subseteq Idl(R),\; I = \bigcap \mathcal{J} \;\Rightarrow\; \exists\, J \in Idl(R),\; J \in \mathcal{J} \;\wedge\; I = J .

Alternatively, II is strongly irreducible if II is proper and, whenever II contains the intersection of two ideals of RR, II contains at least one of those two ideals:

JIdl(R),KIdl(R),IJKIJIK. \forall\, J \in Idl(R),\; \forall\, K \in Idl(R),\; I \supseteq J \cap K \;\Rightarrow\; I \supseteq J \;\vee\; I \supseteq K .

Finally, II is strongly completely irreducible if, whenever II contains the intersection of any collection of ideals of RR, II contains at least one of the ideals in that collection:

𝒥Idl(R),I𝒥JIdl(R),J𝒥IJ. \forall\, \mathcal{J} \subseteq Idl(R),\; I \supseteq \bigcap \mathcal{J} \;\Rightarrow\; \exists\, J \in Idl(R),\; J \in \mathcal{J} \;\wedge\; I \supseteq J .

Every strongly irreducible ideal is irreducible, every completely irreducible ideal is irreducible, and every strongly completely irreducible ideal is both strongly irreducible and completely irreducible. (The converses of these hold in various situations that we should describe below.)

The definition of ‘completely irreducible’ doesn't need to explicitly require II to be proper; that is covered by considering the empty collection? 𝒥\mathcal{J} of ideals. The definition of ‘irreducible’ can take care of that automatically too if it is made unbiased:

Definition

An ideal II of RR is irreducible if, whenever II equals the intersection of a finite list of ideals of RR, II equals at least one of the ideals in the list:

n,JIdl(R) n,I= k[n]J kk[n],I=J k. \forall\, n \in \mathbb{N},\; \forall\, J \in Idl(R)^n,\; I = \bigcap_{k\in[n]} J_k \;\Rightarrow\; \exists\, k \in [n],\; I = J_k .

Also, II of RR is strongly irreducible if, whenever II contains the intersection of a finite list of ideals of RR, II contains at least one of the ideals in the list:

n,JIdl(R) n,I k[n]J kk[n],IJ k. \forall\, n \in \mathbb{N},\; \forall\, J \in Idl(R)^n,\; I \supseteq \bigcap_{k\in[n]} J_k \;\Rightarrow\; \exists\, k \in [n],\; I \supseteq J_k .

As is typical, the case for n>2n \gt 2 follows from the case for n=2n = 2 by induction, the case for n=2n = 2 is the significant requirement in the unbiased definition, the case for n=1n = 1 is trivial, and the case for n=0n = 0 is the extra requirement (in this case, being proper) that rules out ideals that are too irreducible to be irreducible.

As with prime ideals, it may be helpful to focus on the complements of the ideals involved, which are known (especially in constructive mathematics) as anti-ideals. Of course, we could just repeat the definitions involving the join-semilattice AIdl(R)AIdl(R) of antiideals of RR (which classically is equivalent to Idl(R) opIdl(R)^op); I won't write that out here, but it does make the term ‘irreducible’ have more of the flavour of its usual meaning; a proper anti-ideal is irreducible if it cannot be reduced as the union of two smaller anti-ideals.

Properties

If Idl(R)Idl(R) is a distributive lattice, then irreducible ideals are the same as strongly irreducible ideals. If RR is a distributive lattice, then not only are these the same, but the prime ideals are also the same as them.

An ideal generated by an irreducible element is irreducible, but not always conversely (not even if we ignore 00).

References

  • Kiyoshi Iséki. 1956. Ideal Theory of Semiring. Proceedings of the Japan Academy A 32:8, 554–559. Project Euclid.

Last revised on October 13, 2024 at 06:23:47. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.