Let be an abstract rewriting system, i.e., a set equipped with a binary relation . Write for the reflexive-transitive closure of . We say that is locally confluent, alternatively is Church-Rosser, iff for every such that and , there exists such that and .
Given an abstract rewriting system, notated as above, let denote the relation whereby if and . This relation is transitive if is antisymmetric.
Recall that a subset is -inductive if
Define an element to be normal if implies . Equivalently, is normal if there is no for which . Write for the predicate “ is normal”.
In a locally confluent rewriting system , and under the assumption that is antisymmetric, the set
is a -inductive set.
For given , suppose the inductive hypothesis is true: that for every with , there is a unique normal such that . Then by transitivity , so for at least one normal . If and and are normal, then there are chains
Note that implies by inductive hypothesis, so assume instead . Then by local confluence, there is with and . We have by transitivity and antisymmetry of , hence by inductive hypothesis. Since also , we have by the uniqueness clause for . Similarly , so . Hence for a unique normal , and the induction goes through.
Call an abstract rewriting system strongly normalizing if satisfies the ascending chain condition, i.e., if any countably infinite chain
eventually stabilizes (for some , for all ). It is clear that strong normalization implies antisymmetry. Again writing if and , strong normalization implies there are no infinite descending chains (no infinite descent)
In other words, is a well-founded relation (assuming classical logic).
(Newman’s lemma) An abstract rewriting system that is locally confluent and strongly normalizing has the property that for every element there is a unique normal element for which .
By Proposition , the set is -inductive, and since is well-founded under the strong normalization hypothesis, this set is the entirety of .
Franz Baader, Tobias Nipkow: Term Rewriting and All That, Cambridge University Press (1998) [doi:10.1017/CBO9781139172752]
M.H.A. Newman, On theories with a combinatorial definition of “equivalence”, Annals of Mathematics, 43(2):223–243, 1942.
Wikipedia, Newman’s lemma. link
Last revised on June 29, 2025 at 11:59:05. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.