User “Buschi Sergio” at MathOverflow referred to a remark given in a paper by Stefan Schwede and Brooke Shipley (which, according to a comment by David White, the authors credit to Charles Rezk):
Let be a complete, cocomplete, symmetric monoidal closed category, and let be a commutative monoid with respect to the symmetric monoidal product. Then the category of left -modules carries (under the expected definitions) a symmetric monoidal closed structure.
We will denote the monoidal product in by , the symmetry isomorphism by , and the internal hom in by .
A full proof of this, starting from scratch and proceeding in a hands-on way, is somewhat long-winded. But, let’s start from the evident construction of the internal hom for , which for two left -modules , (with actions denoted and ) is given by an equalizer diagram in
where is the evident composite
Buschi Sergio’s specific question (see below) was then how to prove (or how to find a reference for) the assertion that (the putative internal hom in ) is realized as living in . As I said in my answer, the basic idea is to restrict an evident1 -module structure on (induced from ; see below) to the subobject .
In my answer, I claimed that the assertion should be seen as essentially “obvious”, and that it can be proven more or less as it would be in the familiar case where , where we can just rely on elements. I had also written down a sequence of equations between terms that suggest an elements-based proof of this claim:
I still stand by what I said, but before continuing, two remarks:
Ultimately it is justifiable (if a bit hand-wavy) to say that these equations provide a scaffold for a proof in the general case. There are various formalisms for effecting the transition between the elementwise approach and a general proof using commutative diagrams, using one of various “languages for monoidal categories” (e.g., Barry Jay’s). Indeed, one can develop a lambda-calculus adapted to multiplicative intuitionistic linear logic (MILL), and translate the equations above into equations between such lambda terms, and then invoke soundness and completeness of that lambda calculus for MILL to prove theorems in the language of smc categories. But possibly such meta-theory will not satisfy readers who want a more hands-on approach.
The theorem itself is a special case of a much more general result, tracing back to early work of Anders Kock on commutative monads (which Buschi Sergio recognizes, but apparently doesn’t want to rely on).
In the end, I decided it might be more satisfactory to Buschi Sergio if I stopped waving my hands and instead got them dirty. Okay then, I’ll bite the bullet and give a hands-on proof via commutative diagrams.
I would like to permit myself one luxury, however: the Kelly-Mac Lane theorem which gives a simple criterion for commutativity for a large class of diagrams in symmetric monoidal closed categories. This theorem is about diagrams in free symmetric monoidal closed categories generated by a set of letters, in which objects are formal expressions constructed by starting with letters in and forming words using and . We must also include a constant standing for the monoidal unit, but for the form of the Kelly-Mac Lane theorem which we will use, we are only concerned with words in which does not occur. Such words will be called unit-free. Letter-occurrences in a word form a multi-set denoted ; unions of such multi-sets formed by adding multiplicities are denoted .
Let be the free symmetric monoidal closed category generated by a countably infinite set of letters. Let be morphisms in between unit-free words where each letter occurring in occurs exactly twice. Then .
For example, by this theorem there is exactly one morphism in of shape
(namely the internal evaluation map). In this example, the morphism is natural in the variable and extranatural in the variable ; in general, the two occurrences of each letter appearing in the domain/codomain of such “every-variable-twice” morphisms are connected via naturality or extranaturality, so the theorem roughly says that any two smc-definable transformations having the same (extra)natural form must be equal – a kind of coherence theorem.
The typical way this theorem is applied is where one considers two legs of a diagram, in a general smc category , formed from the smc data of , and one recognizes one leg as an instantiation or value of a morphism under an smc functor (uniquely determined by assigning object-values in to letters), and the other leg as an instantiation under the same . If and have the same unit-free domain and codomain and are every-variable-twice, the diagram commutes.
Thus far, we have an enrichment
which we want to lift through the monadic functor . Recall that given an -module , there is a canonical -module structure on given by
where the first map is evident. (Indeed, in any smc category there is a canonical map
natural in the three variables .) We wish to show that the -action on restricts to an -action on .
We thus consider the following diagram (where and are “evident” maps; expresses enriched functoriality of ):
Given that is the equalizer of the two maps shown, the composite equalizes those two maps (and therefore factors through , yielding the arrow indicated by the ? symbol that is to be the -action on ).
The rectangle expressed by the equation
commutes.
The left rectangle in the diagram
commutes by (extra)naturality of . The right rectangle commutes by functoriality of .
Referring back to the diagram in the theorem, it follows that
where the second equation uses functoriality of and the fact that equalizes the pair .
The following diagram commutes:
By the Kelly-Mac Lane theorem. Both legs of the diagram are instances of maps of the form
(substituting for and , for , and for ), so the diagram commutes.
The following diagram commutes, where is the multiplication on the commutative monoid :
The upper left diagram commutes by the preceding lemma. The upper right square commutes by naturality of . The lower triangle commutes by commutativity of the monoid (and functoriality of ). The lower square commutes by the associativity condition on the action (and by functoriality of ).
Recall that we are trying to show
The first equation below picks up where we left off in equation (1)
which completes the proof.
From there, given the action thus produced, it is routine that the module axioms are satisfied, since the module equations hold on the action and we are simply restricting that action.
All uses of the word “evident” indicate that something is being left to the reader. Usually that something is labeled by a nondescript Greek letter like . ↩