Natural: endogenous: produced by factors inside the system
Throughout this page, we shall often denote by the set of objects of a category and by the map induced by a functor .
If and are categories, we shall say that a functor is an isofibration if for every object and every isomorphism with source , there exists an isomorphism with source such that ,
When the isomorphism is uniquely determined by a pair , we shall say that the isofibration has the unique lifting property.
The notion of isofibration is self dual: a functor is an isofibration iff the opposite functor is an isofibration (exercise ). Hence a functor is an isofibration iff for every object and every isomorphism with target , there exists an isomorphism with target such that ,
Let be the groupoid generated by one isomorphism . Then a functor is an isofibration iff it has the right lifting property with respect to the inclusion (resp. ). (exercise ).
We shall say that a functor is monic (resp. surjective, bijective) on objects if the map induced by is injective (resp. surjective, bijective).
Let us denote by the category of small categories and by the category of locally small categories. The category cannot carry a model structure since it is not finitely cocomplete. However,
Let us denote by the class of functors monic on objects in the category , by the class of equivalences, and by the class of isofibrations. Then the pairs and are weak factorisation systems in . If
then the triple is a model structure on the category . The model structure is cartesian closed and proper. We shall say that it is the natural model structure on .
The proof will be given after Proposition .
The class has the three-for-two property and it is closed under retracts.
Let us write to indicate that the functors are isomorphic in the category . The relation is compatible with composition on both sides: we have
for every functor and every functor . We can thus construct a quotient category by putting
for locally small categories and . The canonical functor takes a functor to its isomorphism class in the category of functors . The morphism is invertible iff the functor is an equivalence of categories. It follows that the class has the three-for-two property, since this is true of the class of isomorphisms in any category. Similarly, the class is closed under retracts, since this is true of the class of isomorphisms in any category.
For any functor , any map and any family of isomorphisms there exists a unique functor extending for which the family becomes a natural isomorphism .
The functor takes a map in to the unique map in for which the following diagram commutes,
We shall say that the functor is obtained by transporting the functor along the family of isomorphisms . The possibility of transporting a functor along a family of isomorphisms actually means that the restriction functor is an isofibration with unique lifting, where denote the discrete category whose objects are the elements of .
A functor is monic iff it is monic on objects and faithful. We shall say that a functor is surjective if it is surjective on objects and full.
A surjective equivalence is a split epimorphism; more precisely, every section of the map can be extended uniquely as a section of the functor . There then is a unique isomorphism such that . Dually, a monic equivalence is a split monomorphism. If is a retraction, then there is a unique isomorphism such that .
Let us prove the first statement. Let be an equivalence surjective on objects. The map has a section, since it is surjective. Let be a section. If is a morphism in , then there is a unique morphism in such that , since the map induced by is bijective. This defines a functor . It is easy to see that we have . The functor is an equivalence of categories, since is an equivalence. The existence and uniqueness of an isomorphism such that follows. Let us prove the second statement. The functor is essentially surjective, since it is fully faithful. Thus, for each object we can choose an object together with an isomorphism , with the proviso that when . The proviso implies that for every object , since is monic. There is then a unique functor extending for which the family becomes a natural isomorphism . By construction, the functor takes a morphism in to the unique morphism such that the following square commutes,
If , where is a morphism in , then we have , since the morphisms are units when and the following square commutes,
This shows that . The functor is an equivalence, since is an equivalence. The existence and uniqueness of an isomorphism such that follows.
The class of isofibrations is closed under composition, retracts and base changes.
Let be the groupoid generated by one isomorphism . Then a functor is an isofibration iff it has the right lifting property with respect to the inclusion . Thus, the class of isofibrations is of the form . The result then follows from the proposition here.
An equivalence is an isofibration iff it is surjective on objects. The class of equivalences surjective on objects is closed under composition, retracts and base changes.
Let us prove the first statement. Let be an equivalence which is an isofibration. Then for every object , there exists an object together with an isomorphism , since an equivalence is essentially surjective. There is then an isomorphism such that , since is an isofibration. We then have , and this shows that is surjective on objects. Conversely, let us show that an equivalence surjective on objects is an isofibration. If is an object of and is an isomorphism in , then there exists an object such that , since is surjective on object. The map induced by is bijective, since is an equivalence. Hence there exists a morphism such that . The morphism is invertible, since is invertible and is an equivalence.
This shows that is an isofibration. The first statement of the proposition is proved. Let us prove the second statement. Observe that a functor is an equivalence surjective on objects iff it is fully faithful and surjective on objects. Hence the class of equivalences surjective on objects is the intersection of two classes: the class of fully faithful functors and the class of functors surjective on objects. The class is the right class of the Gabriel factorisation system by the Example here. It then follows from the propositions here and here that the class is closed under composition, retracts and base changes. The class of surjections in the category of sets has the same closure properties, hence also the class .
Suppose that we have a commutative square of categories and functors
in which the functor is monic on objects and the functor is an isofibration. If or is an equivalence, then the square has a diagonal filler.
For this it suffices to show that the left hand square of the following diagram has a diagonal filler,
The projection is an isofibration by Lemma , since it is a base change of the functor . Moreover, is an equivalence when is an equivalence by Lemma{trivialfibrationclosure}. This shows that problem can be reduced to the case of a square
Let us first consider the case where the functor is an equivalence. It follows from Lemma that the functor admits a retraction together with a natural isomorphism such that . This last condition means that we have for every object . We have for every object , since . We thus have a diagram,
There exists an isomorphism with source such that , since the functor is an isofibration by assumption,
This defines a map , where is the target of . The isomorphism can be taken to be a unit when , since is a unit in this case. We then have for every . If we transport the functor by Lemma along the the family of isomorphisms we obtain a functor equipped with an isomorphism . By construction, the functor takes a morphism in to the unique morphism in such that the following square commutes,
It is then a routine matter to verify that we have and . We have proved that the square (2) has a diagonal filler in the case where is an equivalence. Let us now consider the case where is an equivalence. The functor is surjective on objects in this case by Lemma . Hence the following square in the category of sets
has a diagonal filler , since is monic on objects and the pair is a weak factorisation system in the category of sets. It then follows from Lemma that the functor admits a unique section which extends the map , since is a surjective equivalence. It is then a routine matter to verify that we have . We have proved that the square (2) has a diagonal filler in the case where is an equivalence.
Let be the groupoid generated by one isomorphism . We shall denote the inclusion as a map and the inclusion as a map . This is in accordance with the standard notation for the maps in the category , since takes the value and takes the value .
The path object? of a category is defined to be the category . An object of this category is an isomorphism in the category , and a morphism between and is a pair of maps in a commutative square
The functor is the source functor which which takes an isomorphism to its source , and is the target functor which which takes an isomorphism to its target . If denotes the functor , then the functor is the unit functor which takes an object to the unit isomorphism . The relation implies that we have . The functors and are equivalences of categories, since the functors and are equivalences.
The functor
is an isofibration and the functor is an equivalence of categories. Moreover, the functors and are equivalences surjective on objects.
Let us show that the functor is an isofibration. Let be an object of and let be an isomorphism in . There is then a unique isomorphism such that the square (3) commutes. The pair defines an isomorphism in the category , and we have . This proves that is an isofibration. We saw above that the functor and are equivalences of categories. The functor is surjective on objects, since . Similarly, the functor is surjective on objects.
The mapping path object? of a functor is the category defined by the following pullback square
There is a (unique) functor such that and since square (4) is cartesian and we have . Let us put . Then we have
since This is the mapping path factorisation? of the functor . Let us describe the category explicitly. Let us first show that we have a pullback square,
The square commutes, since . To see that it is cartesian, consider the diagram
The right hand square of this diagram is trivially cartesian. The composite square is cartesian by definition of . Hence the left hand square is also cartesian by the lemma here. This shows that the square (5) is cartesian. We now use it for describing the objects and morphisms of the category . By construction, an object of is a triple , where is an object of , is an object of and is an isomorphism . The object can be pictured as a leg with the upper part in and with its foot in :
We have , and . A morphism in the category is a pair of maps and such that the square foot of the following diagram commutes,
The functor takes an object to a leg with a very short foot,
The mapping path category can be constructed as the pseudo-pullback? of the functor with the identity functor .
The functor in the mapping path factorisation
is an isofibration and the functor is an equivalence monic on objects.
Let us show that the functor is an isofibration. We first give a formal proof by using the general argumentation of Quillen. The functor is a base change of the functor , since the square (5) is cartesian. Hence the functor is an isofibration by Proposition , since the functor is an isofibration by Proposition . The projection is a base change of the functor . It is thus an isofibration, since the functor is (trivially) an isofibration. It follows that the composite is an isofibration, since the class of isofibrations is closed under composition by Proposition . Let us now give the bare foot proof. For every object and every isomorphism the pair is an isomorphism and we have ,
This proves that is an isofibration. It remains to prove that the functor is an equivalence monic on objects. It is certainly monic on objects, since we have . Let us show that it is an equivalence. Again, we shall give two proofs, the first by using the general argumentation of Quillen. It suffices to prove that the functor is an equivalence by three-for-two, since we have . But the functor is a base change of the functor , since the square (4) is cartesian. The functor is an equivalence surjective on objects by Proposition . It follows that the functor is an equivalence by Proposition . Let us now gives the bare foot proof that the functor is an equivalence. For this it suffices to exibit a natural isomorphism since we already have . But and the pair defines a natural isomorphism ,
The class of functors monic on objects is closed under composition, retracts and cobase changes.
The class of injective maps in the category of sets is closed under composition, retracts and cobase changes. Hence also the class of functors monic on objects.
The category admits a weak factorisation system in which is the class of equivalences monic on objects and is the class of isofibrations.
We shall use the characterisation of weak factorisation systems here. The mapping path category of a functor is locally small if the category is locally small, since the functor is an equivalence by Proposition . It then follows from this proposition that every functor in admits a -factorisation. By Lemma we have . It remains to verify that the classes and are closed under retracts. This is true for the class by Proposition . And this is true for the class of functors monic on objects by Lemma . Moreover, a retract of an equivalence is an equivalence by Lemma .
The class of equivalences monic on objects is closed under composition, retracts and cobase changes.
The class of equivalences monic on objects is the left class of a weak factorisation system by Proposition . It is thus closed under composition, retracts and cobase changes.
The cylinder? of a category is defined to be the category . We shall denote the inclusion by , the inclusion by , and the projection by . Notice that .
The functor is monic on objects and the projection is an equivalence. Moreover, the functors and are equivalences monic on objects.
I spare you the proof.
The mapping cylinder? of a functor is the category defined by the following pushout square:
There is a (unique) functor such that and , since square (6) is cocartesian and we have . Let us put . Then we have
since . This is the mapping cylinder factorisation? of the functor . Let us show that we have a pushout square,
The square commutes since . The square is a pushout, since both the top square and the composite square of the following diagram are cocartesian,
In the mapping cylinder factorisation,
the functor is monic on objects and the functor is an equivalence surjective on objects.
The functor is a cobase change of the functor , since the square (7) is cocartesian. Hence the functor is monic on objects by Proposition , since the functor is monic on objects by Proposition . It follows that the functor is monic on objects since the functor is monic on objects. Let us now show that the functor is an equivalence surjective on objects. The functor is obviously surjective on objects, since we have . In order to show that it is an equivalence, it suffices to show that the functor is an equivalence by three-for-two. But is a cobase change of the functor , since the square (6) is cocartesian. It follows that the functor is an equivalence by the Proposition , since is an equivalence monic on objects by Proposition .
The category admits a weak factorisation system in which is the class functors monic on objects and is the class of acyclic isofibration.
We shall use the characterisation of weak factorisation systems here. The mapping cylinder of a functor is locally small if the category is locally small, since the functor is an equivalence by Proposition . The same proposition shows that every functor admits a -factorisation. It follows from Lemma that we have . The class is closed under codomain retracts by Corollary . Also the class by Lemma .
The class of equivalences in has the three-for-two property by Lemma . The pair is a weak factorisation system by Proposition , and the pair is a weak factorisation system by Proposition . This completes the proof that the triple is a model structure on the category . Every object of this model structure is fibrant and cofibrant, since the map is an isofibration and the map is monic on objects. Hence the model structure is proper by a proposition [here]. Let us show that the model structure is cartesian closed. If and , are two functors, consider the functor
obtained from the commutative square
Let us show that the functor is a cofibration if and are cofibrations, and that it is a an equivalence if in addition or is an equivalence. We have , since the functor preserves cartesian products and pushouts (it is actually continuous and cocontinuous). But the map is monic, if and are monic by a result [here]. This shows that is a cofibration if and are cofibrations. If in addition is an equivalence, then so are the vertical maps in the square, since the class of equivalences is closed under products. Consider the following diagram with a pushout square on the left hand side,
The functor is an acyclic cofibration by cobase change, since the functor is. Hence the functor is acyclic by three-for-two, since the functors and are acyclic.
If and , are two functors, consider the functor
obtained from the commutative square
Recall that the category is locally small (resp. small) if is small and is locally small (resp. small).
The functor is an isofibration, if the functor is an isofibration and the functor is monic on objects. Moreover, the functor is an equivalence, if in addition one of the fonctors or is an equivalence.
Recall that a functor between small categories is said to be a Morita equivalence if the inverse image functor
is an equivalence of categories. A functor is a Morita equivalence iff it is fully faithful and every object is a retract of an object in the image of .
Recall an idempotent in a category is said to split if there exists a pair of morphisms and such that and . We shall say that is Karoubi complete if every idempotent in splits.
Let be the category freely generated by two arrows and such that . And let be the category freely generated by one idempotent . Then the functor which takes to is fully faithful.
We shall say that a functor is an idfibration if it has the right liffting property with respect to the inclusion . A category is Karoubi complete iff the functor is an idfibration.
An idfibration is an isofibration. It is easy to see that an isofibration is an idfibration iff the functor reflects split idempotents, that is, if the implication
is true for every idempotent .
The category of small categories admits a model structure in which is the class of functors monic on objects, is the class of Morita equivalences and is the class of idfibrations. The model structure is cartesian closed and left proper. We shall say that it is the Karoubian model structure on the category .
Show that the notion of isofibration is self-dual: a functor is an isofibration iff the opposite functor is an isofibration.
Show that a functor is an isofibration iff it has the right lifting property with respect to the inclusion .