This is a paper that John Baez and Todd Trimble are writing. There is a followup, Schur functors II.
Classically, a Schur functor is a specific sort of functor
where is the category of finite-dimensional complex space. Namely, it is one where is obtained by taking a tensor power of , say , and then picking out the subspace that transforms according to a particular irreducible representation of the symmetric group , which acts on by permuting the tensor factors.
Irreducible complex representations of correspond to -box Young diagrams, so Schur functors are usually described with the help of these. An -box Young diagram is simply a handy notation for a way of writing as a sum of natural numbers written in decreasing order. For example, this 17-box Young diagram:
describes the partition of as . However, it also can be used to construct an irreducible complex representation of the permutation group , and thus a Schur functor.
The relation between Young diagrams and Schur functors can be described using the group algebra of the symmetric group, . Given an -box Young diagram , we can think of the operation ‘symmetrize with respect to permutations of the boxes in each row’ as an element . Similarly, we can think of the operation ‘antisymmetrize with respect to permutations of the boxes in each column’ as an element . By construction, each of these elements is idempotent:
Now, it is easy to see that the product of commuting idempotents is idempotent. The elements and do not commute, but amazingly, their product
is still idempotent! The reason is that commutes with all permutations, so it lies in the center of the group algebra. This ensures that
Checking that commutes with all permutations is a calculation everyone must do for themselves.
This element is called the Young symmetrizer corresponding to the -box Young diagram . Since the group algebra acts on by permuting the factors, the Young symmetrizer gives a projection
whose range is a subspace called . Since commutes with everything in , this subspace is invariant under the action of , and — as already mentioned — it is a direct sum of copies of a specific irreducible representation of . But the point is this: there is a functor, called a Schur functor:
which has precisely this effect on objects:
More generally, any finite direct sum of the Schur functors just described may also be called a Schur functor. For example:
For each , the tensor power is a Schur functor.
If and are Schur functors, of course the functor is a Schur functor.
If and are Schur functors, the functor is also a Schur functor.
If and are Schur functors, the composite is a Schur functor. This way of constructing Schur functors is known as plethysm.
There is a category with these more general Schur functors as objects and natural transformations between them as morphisms. In this article we would like to give a conceputal explanation of this category and some of its generalizations.
For starters, we can replace the complex numbers by any field of characteristic zero, and everything in our discussion still works. Even better, the resulting category has has a nice description in terms of groupoid of finite sets and bijections. We will find it convenient to work with a skeleton of this groupoid, namely the permutation groupoid:
where objects are natural numbers, all morphisms are automorphisms, and the automorphisms of the object form the group . In these terms, is equivalent to the category where:
objects are functors such that for all sufficiently large ;
morphisms are natural transformations.
This allows us to think of as a subcategory of the category of representations of , by which we simply mean functors . Every irreducible representation of is finite-dimensional: it is really just an irreducible representation of some group . Every representation of is a direct sum of these irreducibles. may be identified with the full subcategory consisting of finite direct sums of irreducibles.
We have described Schur functors as special functors
But in fact, these functors make sense much more broadly. In fact they can be applied to any ‘symmetric monoidal Cauchy complete linear category’. Here by linear category we mean a category enriched over , the category of vector spaces over a fixed field of characteristic zero. A symmetric monoidal linear category is a symmetric monoidal category where the tensor product distributes over the linear structure on morphisms. Such a category is Cauchy complete when:
it has biproducts, also known as direct sums, and
idempotents split.
To illustrate the full breadth of this generalization, here are a few examples:
the category , consisting of vector spaces over any field of characteristic zero
the category , consisting of finite-dimensional vector spaces over
the category of representations of any group on vector spaces (or finite-dimensional vector spaces) over
the category of super vector spaces, graded vectors or chain complexes over
for or , the category of finite-dimensional real or complex vector bundles over any topological space, or smooth vector bundles over any smooth manifold
the category of algebraic vector bundles over any algebraic variety (or more generally, scheme or algebraic stack) over
the category of coherent sheaves of vector spaces over any algebraic variety (or scheme or algebraic stack) over
These examples can be hybridized, and thus they multiply indefinitely: for example, we could take coherent sheaves of chain complexes, or vector bundles equipped with a group action, and so on.
In the following subsections, we explain how to define Schur functors on any category of this sort. A somewhat novel feature of our treatment is that we do not require the theory of Young diagrams to define and study Schur functors.
Our strategy is as follows. We fix a symmetric monoidal Cauchy complete linear category, . The group algebra begins life as a monoid in the symmetric monoidal category . However, we shall explain how interpret it as living in by a “change of base” functor going from to . This will let us use the Young symmetrizers to construct idempotents on for any object . Splitting these idempotents, we obtain the Schur functors .
To achieve the desired change of base, let be the linear category whose objects are integers and whose morphisms are matrices with entries in . Because is Cauchy complete and in particular has finite biproducts (direct sums), there is an evident linear functor
which takes to , the direct sum of copies of the tensor unit . It is the unique linear functor taking to , up to unique linear isomorphism. In the case , the linear functor
taking to , is a linear equivalence (exhibiting as a skeleton of ). Because of this equivalence, we could equally well say that there is a linear functor
which, up to unique linear isomorphism, is the unique linear functor taking to . Notice that a symmetric monoidal functor of this form must take the tensor unit to (up to coherent isomorphism, as always), and in fact is symmetric monoidal, because there is a canonical isomorphism
using the fact that preserves direct sums in each argument, and the fact that there is a canonical isomorphism .
In summary, we have the following proposition.
There is exactly one symmetric monoidal linear functor , up to symmetric monoidal linear isomorphism.
Next we explain how given an object , any Young symmetrizer in acts as an idempotent on .
For this we only need to know a little bit about the group algebra , which we recall here. By Maschke’s theorem, for any finite group , the group algebra decomposes as a direct sum of matrix algebras
where ranges over isomorphism classes of irreducible representations of . The identity elements of these matrix algebras thus correspond to certain special elements . Clearly these elements are idempotent:
We are particularly interested in the case . In this case, we call the idempotents are ‘Young symmetrizers’. However, we will not need the formula for these idempotents.
The key step is to apply base change to . Here we exploit the fact that
is a monoid in the monoidal category . Since is a monoidal functor, it follows that carries to a monoid in , which we again call by abuse of notation. As an object of , we have
There is a general concept of what it means for a monoid in a monoidal category to act on an object in that category. In particular, if is an object of , the monoid acts on the tensor power . To see this, note that for each , there is a corresponding symmetry isomorphism
Putting these together with the help of (1) we obtain a morphism
which is the desired action.
Finally, we would like to describe how each Young symmetrizer acts on . Quite generally, any element gives a linear map from to , namely the unique map sending to . Applying the functor to this, we obtain a morphism which by abuse of language we call
This then yields an endomorphism
given as the composite
It is easy to check that for any ,
Thus for any Young symmetrizer , the morphism
is idempotent, because is.
By construction, the morphisms
are the components of a natural transformation from the functor to itself. Since idempotents split in , we can form the cokernel of , or in other words, the coequalizer of the pair
For any Young diagram , the Schur functor is defined as follows. Given an object of , let be the cokernel of . Given a morphism in , let be the unique map such that
commutes, where the horizontal arrows are the cokernel maps.
More generally we can define a Schur functor
for any finite-dimensional representation of , as follows. We can write as a finite direct sum of irreducible representations:
and then define
Suppose now that we have a symmetric monoidal linear functor . We can think of as a “change of base category”, and Schur functors are “natural” with respect to change of base.
That is to say: if is a symmetric monoidal linear functor , then by definition preserves tensor products (at least up to coherent natural isomorphism), and will automatically preserve both direct sums (by linearity) as well as splittings of idempotents (as all functors do). Therefore, for a Schur functor , we have natural isomorphisms
where the first isomorphism uses the symmetric monoidal structure of ; the second uses the fact that because there is, up to isomorphism, only one symmetric monoidal linear functor ; the third uses the symmetric monoidal structure again and preservation of idempotent splittings.
If is any representation, then by writing as a direct sum of irreducible representations and using the fact that preserves direct sums, we have more generally
In summary, Schur functors transfer “naturally” across change of base functors .
As we have seen, Schur functors are definable under fairly mild hypotheses: working over a field of characteristic zero, they can be defined on any symmetric monoidal linear category which is Cauchy complete. So, for such we can define a Schur functor
and moreover, if is a symmetric monoidal linear functor, the Schur functors on and are “naturally” compatible, in the sense that the diagram
commutes up to a canonical isomorphism , and moreover these fit together sensibly when we compose symmetric monoidal linear functors.
In this abstract framework, it may be wondered what significant role is played by the representations of the symmetric group. The natural isomorphisms which relate the Schur functors across change of base are pleasant to observe, but surely this is just some piddling general nonsense in the larger story of Schur functors , which are after all deeply studied and incredibly rich classical constructions?
Let us put the question another way. We have seen the Schur functors are constructed in a uniform (or “polymorphic”) way across all symmetric monoidal Cauchy complete linear categories , and this construction is natural with respect to symmetric monoidal change of base functors . Or rather: not natural in a strict sense, but pseudonatural in the sense that naturality squares commute up to isomorphism . Now pseudonaturality is a very general phenomenon in 2-category theory. So the question is: among all such pseudonatural transformations , what is special about the Schur functors ? What extra properties pick out exactly the Schur functors from the class of all pseudonatural transformations ?
The perhaps surprising answer is: no extra properties! That is, the Schur functors are precisely those functors that are defined on all symmetric monoidal Cauchy complete linear and that are pseudonatural with respect to change of base !
Let us now make this precise. Schur functors are defined on certain symmetric monoidal linear categories, but they respect neither the symmetric monoidal structure nor the linear structure. So, we have to forget some of the structure of the objects on which Schur functors are defined. This focuses our attention on the ‘forgetful’ 2-functor
where:
SymMonLinCauch is the 2-category with
small symmetric monoidal Cauchy complete linear categories as objects,
symmetric monoidal linear functors as morphisms,
symmetric monoidal linear natural transformations as 2-morphisms.
As we shall see, Schur functors correspond to pseudonatural transformations from to itself, and morphisms between Schur functors correspond to modifications between these pseudonatural transformations. For the reader unaccustomed to these 2-categorical concepts, we recall:
Given two 2-functors between 2-categories, a pseudonatural transformation is a rule that assigns to each 0-cell of a 1-cell of , and to each 1-cell of an invertible 2-cell of :
such that the following pasting diagram equalities hold:
and
With notation as above, let be two pseudonatural transformations. A modification is a rule which associates to each 0-cell of a 2-cell of , such that the following compatibility condition holds:
tincan.png:pic
We now propose our conceptual definition of Schur functor:
An (abstract) Schur functor is a pseudonatural transformation , where
is the forgetful 2-functor. A morphism of Schur functors is a modification between such pseudonatural transformations.
What this proposed definition makes manifestly obvious is that Schur functors are closed under composition. This provides a satisfying conceptual explanation of plethysm, as we will explore in the next two sections. However, we should first check that this proposed definition gives a category of Schur functors equivalent to the category defined earlier!
Before launching into the proof, it is worth pondering an easier problem where we replace categories by sets, and symmetric monoidal linear Cauchy-complete categories by commutative rings. So, instead of let us consider , and instead of let us consider . There is a forgetful functor
What are the natural transformations from this functor to itself? Any polynomial defines such a natural transformation, since for any commutative ring there is a function given by
and this is clearly natural in . But in fact, the set of natural transformations from this functor turns out to be precisely . And the reason is that is the free commutative ring on one generator!
To see this, note that the forgetful functor
has a left adjoint, the ‘free commutative ring’ functor
The free commutative ring on a 1-element set is
and homomorphisms from to any commutative ring are in one-to-one correspondence with elements of the underlying set of , since
So, we say represents the functor . This makes it easy to show that the set of natural transformations from to itself is isomorphic to the underlying set of , namely :
In the first step here we use the representability ; in the second we use the Yoneda lemma, and in the third we use the adjointness between and .
We shall carry out a categorified version of this argument to prove that is the category of endomorphisms of the 2-functor
The key is that is the free symmetric monoidal linear Cauchy-complete category on one generator.
To build a bridge from abstract Schur functors as pseudonatural transformations to the more classical descriptions, we start with the following key result. In what follows we use to denote the ‘linearization’ of the permutation groupoid: that is, the linear category formed by replacing the homsets in by the free vector spaces on those homsets. We use to denote the Cauchy completion of the linearization of . As we shall see, is equivalent to the category of Schur functors. But first:
The underlying 2-functor
is represented by . In other words:
It is well-known that the permutation category , whose objects are integers and whose morphisms are precisely automorphisms given by permutation groups , is the representing object for the underlying 2-functor
Let denote the 2-category of small symmetric monoidal linear (but not necessarily Cauchy complete) categories, and let denote the 2-category of small linear categories. Let denote linearization, given by change of base
applied to a -enriched category to yield a linear category . is left 2-adjoint to the underlying 2-functor . For this, we use the fact that if is a nice closed category (here ) – in particular cocomplete – then the lax monoidal functor has a left adjoint (here linearization) which is strong (symmetric) monoidal. This induces a 2-functor -- which is strong 2-symmetric monoidal. It therefore sends symmetric pseudomonoids in - to symmetric pseudomonoids in -. In other words, it sends symmetric monoidal categories to symmetric monoidal linear categories. Therefore, the 2-adjunction between and lifts to one between and :
Finally, let denote the 2-category of small Cauchy complete linear categories. The linear Cauchy completion gives a 2-reflector which is left 2-adjoint to the 2-embedding , and again the 2-adjunction lifts to the level of symmetric monoidal structure to give a 2-adjunction
For this, the key fact is that if denotes the tensor product of two -enriched categories, then there is a canonical enriched functor making Cauchy completion into a lax 2-monoidal functor on -. Even better, it is lax 2-symmetric monoidal. So, it sends symmetric pseudomonoids to symmetric pseudomonoids. In this case, then, it sends symmetric monoidal linear categories to symmetric monoidal linear Cauchy-complete categories.
Putting this all together, the underlying functor is the evident composite
and therefore we have pseudonatural equivalences
so that is the representing object.
Let us now calculate . In general, the linear Cauchy completion of a linear category consists of the full subcategory of linear presheaves that are obtained as retracts of finite direct sums of representables . In the case , these are the functors
where for large enough . For it is clear that this category contains the representables and is closed under finite direct sums and retracts. On the other hand, every polynomial is a sum of monomials , and by Maschke’s theorem, each -module is the retract of a finite sum of copies of the group algebra which corresponds to the representable .
So, inspired by Joyal’s work on combinatorial species, we make the following definition:
A polynomial species is a functor where for all sufficiently large . A morphism of polynomial species is a natural transformation between such functors.
As we have mentioned, the category of polynomial species inherits two monoidal structures from via Day convolution. Most important is the one coming from the additive monoidal structure on , which is given on the level of objects by adding natural numbers, and on the morphism level given by group homomorphisms
which juxtapose permutations. This can be linearized to give algebra maps
which give the monoidal category structure of . This monoidal structure uniquely extends via Day convolution to the Cauchy completion , which is intermediate between and the category of -valued presheaves on . The general formula for the Day convolution product applied to presheaves is
or, in other notation,
and by restriction this formula gives a tensor product on polynomial species. This tensor product is a kind of categorification of the usual definition of product of ordinary polynomials, where given
the Taylor coefficient of the product is
So in summary:
is equivalent to the symmetric monoidal category of polynomial species.
Now, having defined Schur functors abstractly as pseudonatural transformations , the representability theorem together with the 2-categorical Yoneda lemma means that the category of Schur functors is equivalent to the category of symmetric monoidal linear functors on . Accordingly, we calculate
In other words,
The category is equivalent to the category of polynomial species .
NB: This theorem refers only to the underlying category . In other words, this category certainly has linear tensor category structure as well, but this structure is not respected by Schur functor composition which we consider next.
Now we consider composition of Schur functors , or equivalently symmetric monoidal linear functors . Composition endows with a monoidal structure, and this monoidal structure transfers across the equivalence of the preceding theorem to a monoidal structure on the underlying category of Schur functors, or equivalently, polynomial species . We proceed to analyze this monoidal structure.
It may be easier to do this in reverse. Any Schur functor may regarded as a functor
This induces a symmetric monoidal functor, unique up to (unique) symmetric monoidal isomorphism:
Here is a Day convolution product of copies of . Finally, the functor is linearized and extended (uniquely) to the linear Cauchy completion, to give a symmetric monoidal linear functor on . The efficient tensor product description is
as this manifestly preserves colimits in the blank argument and therefore all colimits needed for the Cauchy completion. (And since the extension to the Cauchy completion is unique, this formula must be correct! The only question is whether this functor is valued in .)
In the language of species, this construction is called the substitution product, and is denoted . This is morally correct because it is indeed an appropriate categorification of polynomial composition. However, to avoid overloading the symbol in ways that might be confusing, we will rename it . Thus,
In notation which looks slightly less abstract, this is the Schur object given by the formula
It should be noted that is indeed for , so that is indeed a polynomial species. It is just the polynomial special case of the substitution product which is defined on general linear species .
The product makes the category of polynomial species into a monoidal category. The unit for this product is polynomial species given by the representable .
The following proof is adapted from a similar argument due to Max Kelly [ref]: we exhibit an associativity isomorphism on the basis of universal properties. The point is that by the universal property of , the category of functors
is equivalent to the category of symmetric monoidal linear functors
The correspondence in one direction takes to the symmetric monoidal functor , and in the other direction takes to . By the equivalence, we have a unit isomorphism . Also by this equivalence, symmetric monoidal linear transformations between symmetric monoidal linear functors of the form
are in natural bijection with morphisms , which by the unit isomorphism reduce to morphisms . Thus, corresponding to the identity on we obtain an associativity map . By similar arguments that appeal to the universal property of , we get all the required axioms: the invertibility of , the pentagon, etc.
To summarize: we have equivalences between
The category of pseudonatural transformations ;
The category of symmetric monoidal linear functors ;
The category .
The equivalence takes a polynomial species to . Moreover, the associativity isomorphism is precisely a structure
of strong monoidal equivalence from to the monoidal category under endofunctor composition. (The hexagonal coherence condition for a monoidal functor follows from the pentagon; one side of the hexagon is an identity since endofunctor composition is a strict monoidal product.)
The tensor product on goes by another name: it is the plethystic tensor product.
William Fulton, Young Tableaux, with Applications to Representation Theory and Geometry, Cambridge U. Press, 1997.
André Joyal, Une théorie combinatoire des séries formelles, Adv. Math 42 (1981), 1–82.
André Joyal: Foncteurs analytiques et espèces des structures, in Combinatoire Énumérative, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 1234, Springer, Berlin, 1986, pp. 126–159.
François Bergeron, Gilbert Labelle, Pierre Leroux, Combinatorial Species and Tree-like Structures, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge 1998.
Marcelo Aguiar and Swapneel Mahajan, Monoidal functors, species and Hopf algebras, available online.
There is also some old material that may still be useful.
Last revised on July 31, 2013 at 16:51:06. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.