This entry is about the small category named after Graeme Segal. Not to be confused with the model in higher category theory called Segal categories.
Segal’s category, denoted by , is the category opposite to the skeleton of the category of pointed finite sets:
Equivalently, is the category opposite to the category of finite sets and partially defined maps. Objects are finite sets. Morphisms are pairs , where and is a map of sets. Identity morphisms are specified by . Composition is defined as follows:
Equivalently (Segal, Definition 1.1), admits the following covariant description. Objects are finite sets. Morphisms are maps such that implies . Identity morphisms are specified by . Composition is defined as follows:
The category is related to (infinity,1)-operads in a way similar to how the simplex category (non-empty and linearly ordered finite sets) is related to (∞,1)-categories.
The categories and are equivalent via the following pair of functors. The functor
sends
The functor
sends
Recall the simplex category , whose objects are finite inhabited totally ordered sets and morphisms are order-preserving maps of sets. We set
Interpreting a simplex as a (posetal) category, a spine edge in is a morphism in that is not an identity morphism and cannot be decomposed as the composition of two nonidentity morphisms. That is to say, in a standard simplex , a spine edge is a pair of the form , , which encodes the morphism .
The canonical functor
sends a simplex to its set of spine edges:
To define on morphisms, observe that a morphism of simplices can be interpreted as a functor between posetal categories. This functor sends a spine edge in to the composition of a set of spine edges in . More specifically, sends a spine edge to the composition of spine edges
Using Segal’s covariant description of , we can define a morphism by sending a spine edge in to the set of spine edges in whose composition yields the image of under the functor .
In terms of the category FinSetPart, we can describe as a partial map of finite sets that sends to the unique pair such that . (If no such pair exists, then is undefined on .)
Given that the category can be used to encode homotopy coherent associative monoids in the same manner that the category can be used to encode homotopy coherent commutative monoids, it is natural to wonder why the description of the comparison functor appears to be so asymmetric. The primary reason for this asymmetry is that the traditional description of the category relies on the fact that elements are composed in a prescribed order, just like morphisms in a category. This enables us to define as a full subcategory of the category of small categories. There is no analogue of such categorical structure for the category .
However, it is possible to give an alternative definition of the category resembling Segal’s covariant formulation and the category FinSetPart. In these formulations, objects encode sets of spine edges (as defined above) instead of sets of vertices.
In the first formulation, the category is defined as the category opposite to the following category. Objects are finite totally ordered sets. Morphisms are pairs , where is an interval in , defined as a triple of disjoint subsets of whose union equals and such that , and is an order-preserving map. The set uniquely determines and unless . The identity morphism on is given by the pair , where . Given morphisms
we define their composition as
where
Now the forgetful functor can be described as the functor that discards the total order on objects and discards the interval on morphisms.
There is also an analog of the covariant description of for the category . In this setting, is the following category. Objects are finite totally ordered sets. Morphisms are maps of sets such that implies and we have . The sets and are uniquely determined by unless the latter is empty. Morphisms are composed like in the category .
Now the forgetful functor can be described as the functor that discards the total order on objects and discards the data of and on morphisms.
The category is a symmetric monoidal category, induced from the cartesian monoidal structure on the category Set:
The reader should keep in mind that is not a product in the category FinSetPart, but only in Set.
In terms of the category , the monoidal structure is given by the smash product of pointed sets:
A Γ-object in a cartesian monoidal category (more generally, cartesian monoidal (∞,1)-category) is a functor
(equivalently, a functor ) such that for all the map
induced by the morphisms
is an equivalence, as is the map . Here denotes the coproduct in the category Set (i.e., disjoint union). It does not denote the coproduct in the category FinSetPart.
Γ-objects in encode -monoids in , i.e., homotopy coherent commutative monoids. See the article Γ-space for more information.
Original reference:
For instance notation 2.0.0.2 in
Last revised on June 12, 2025 at 02:01:42. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.