Temporal logics, as their name suggests, are formal logics that are meant to refer to the passage of time. They form a very large and important class of modal logics, but here we will, to start with, only look at some simple cases. An important early example of a temporal logic is given by Arthur Prior‘s tense logic.
First the basic temporal language is built with two binary model operators, which instead of being denoted ‘box’ and ‘diamond’, are written and . The intended interpretation of these are:
is will be true at some future time;
is was true at some past time.
The reason for the notation and should be clear.
The dual of is , so . This means that we read as ‘at no future time is not true’, i.e., is always going to be true. ( for ‘going’.)
The dual of is written , whence and interprets as ‘ has always been true’. ( is for ‘has’ - which is a bit weak, but that is life!)
If for all we have , then whatever has happened will always have happened, which seems reasonable so this might be a suitable ‘general truth’ we might want a temporal logic to contain.
If we had in our logic that , then this would means that if is true at some future time, then at some future time it will be true that will be true at some future time, so between any two instants there must be a third, and the general truth of this would say something about the ‘internal structure’ of time as modelled by such a logic.
This basic temporal language does not yet really constitute a sensible logic that could model important features of ‘time’. but we can still look at models so as to see what properties of the models can be identified as corresponding to seemingly feasible formulae in the language.
A frame for BTL will be a set, , with two binary relations and . We have reads that ‘at , is in the future’ - but, in the ordinary common sense meaning of words, this should mean and conversely. In other words should be the converse or opposite relation of .
(In general, if is a binary relation on a set , then its opposite relation is defined by
A frame of the form is called a bidirectional frame.
If we have any model with a valuation, , then we can interpret BTL in terms of it by specifying the interpretation of in terms that of . explicitly we define
if and only if
if and only if ,
but, of course, this is still a long way from having a logic that looks as if it captures ‘time-like’ behaviour. We could have models with ‘circular time’, and ‘branching time’. Both of these correspond to various situations in computational applications so should be kept in mind, both to be able to identify their occurrence and to build them in or to avoid them in the logics.
One condition it would be natural to impose is transitivity of , since if is true at some future time, then clearly, itself must also be true at some future time, i.e., later on still! This leads one to ask that
should be in our logic, (and similarly for , but that will hold in the bidirectional models since if is transitive then so will be ).
Instead of points, periods can be thought of as primitive entities. Therefore one may consider structures of the form , where means that the whole period precedes , and is the inclusion relation (see Venema 2017).
Other time structures are described in (Hajnicz 1996, Chapter 2). In particular, a metric cyclic point time structure is defined as:
It can be axiomatized by five axioms (totality, local antisymmetry, local linearity, local transitivity, and consistency) in the first-order predicate calculus.
It is possible to specify a temporal type theory in the context of adjoint logic. Consider a category , and an internal category given by . Here we understand elements of as time intervals, and and as marking their beginning and end points. We may choose to impose additional structure on , e.g., that it be an internal poset, or a linear order.
Now each arrow, and , generates an adjoint triple, e.g., , formed of dependent sum, base change, dependent product, going between the slices and .
Then we find two adjunctions and , e.g.,
Now consider for the moment that and are propositions. Then means “there is some interval beginning now and such that is true at its end”, i.e. ; while means “for all intervals ending now, is true at their beginning”, i.e. . Hence our adjunction is . Similarly, interchanging and , we find . Note that we don’t have to assume the classical principle and .
In the setting of dependent type theory, we do not need to restrict to propositions, but can treat the temporal operators on general time-dependent types. So if is the type of people alive at , is the type of people alive at a point in the future of , and is a function from future times to people alive at that time, e.g., an element of this is ‘The oldest person alive(t)’.
Since is a category, we have in addition to the two projections , composition . This allows us to express more subtle temporal expressions, such as ‘ has been true since a time when was true’, denoted .
(note ). That is, there is a subinterval ending now such that was true at its beginning and was true at all points inside it. Similarly, ‘ will be true until a time when is true’ is
Temporal logicians have debated the relevant advantages of instant-based and interval-based approaches. Some have also considered hybrid approaches (Balb11). The analysis of this section suggests that working with intervals and instants together in the form of an internal category allows for a natural treatment via adjoint logic.
An important construction in interval-based temporal logics is the chop operator, (Venema 1991). This applies to two interval properties, , , so that denotes the property of an interval that it may be divided into two sub-intervals such that holds of the first and of the second. In our current framework we have .
One of the consequences of taking as an internal category is that the future includes the present, so that could be true now and at no other instant but we would have that is true when it is supposed to say “ will be true at some Future time”. Similarly, we would have that holds now if and both hold now (in general, as defined above it requires to still hold at the instant when becomes true).
If we wish to change these consequences, we could let be the -intervals instead of the -ones. In other words, we could take to be a semicategory. While this accords with standard practice, the original alternative has been proposed:
The most common practice in temporal logic is to regard time as an irreflexive ordering, so that “henceforth”, meaning “at all future times”, does not refer to the present moment. On the other hand, the Greek philosopher Diodorus proposed that the necessary be identified with that which is now and will always be the case. This suggests a temporal interpretation of that is naturally formalised by using reflexive orderings. The same interpretation is adopted in the logic of concurrent programs to be discussed. (Gold92, p. 44)
On the other hand, some temporal logicians look to represent both forms of ‘henceforth’.
For an related approach to temporal type theory, see (Schultz-Spivak 17).
In computer science, logics have been devised for dealing with the behaviours of entities undergoing transitions between its states. Where in a linear temporal logic, operators are provided for describing events along a single computation path, in a branching-time logic the temporal operators quantify over the paths that are possible from a given state. The computation tree logic (pronounced “CTL star”) combines both the branching-time operators of and the linear-time operators of .
Starting from a finite-state system, where a finite collection of states represented by the nodes of a graph are connected by labelled edges representing transitions, the path tree of the system can be generated. This presents as a tree all possible paths that the system may undergo from an initial state.
The Computation tree logic is then deployed to reason about the behaviour of the system. This allows for quantification, both universal and existential, over paths. It is also possible to express that a certain state will occur at some point in the future or always in the future.
Now beyond the and operators above, we can express new operators such as ‘necessarily in the future’ to convey that along every path emanating from the current state that some property will hold at some point, and ‘possibly henceforth’ to convey that there is at least one path along which some property holds at every point.
There is a Curry-Howard correspondence between linear-time temporal logic (LTL) and functional reactive programming (FRP) (Jeffrey 12, Jeltsch 12).
Generally this entry is based on
but see also:
A. Galton, Temporal Logic, (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Patrick Blackburn, Tense, Temporal Reference and Tense Logic, Journal of Semantics, 1994,11,
pages 83–101, on-line version
Arthur Prior, 1957, Time and Modality, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Arthur Prior, 1967, Past, Present and Future, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Balbiani, P., Goranko, V. and Sciavicco, G., 2011, ‘Two-sorted Point-Interval Temporal logics’, in Proc. of the 7th International Workshop on Methods for Modalities (M4M7) (Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science: Volume 278), pp. 31–45.
Robert Goldblatt, Logics of time and computation, 1992, (pdf)
For the relationship between linear-time temporal logic and functional reactive programming, see
Alan Jeffrey LTL types FRP: Linear-time temporal logic propositions as types, proofs as functional reactive programs, in: Proceedings of the Sixth Workshop on Programming Languages Meets Program Verification (PLPV ’12)(2012), pp. 49–60. (pdf)
Wolfgang Jeltsch, Towards a Common Categorical Semantics for Linear-Time Temporal Logic and Functional Reactive Programming, Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 286, pp. 229-242, (doi)
Yde Venema, Temporal logic. 2017. (pdf)
For an interval-based approach see
For other time structures see
For versions of temporal type theory see
Patrick Schultz, David Spivak, Temporal Type Theory: A topos-theoretic approach to systems and behavior, (arXiv:1710.10258)
David Corfield, Modal homotopy type theory, Oxford University Press 2020, Sec. 4.3 (ISBN: 9780198853404)
Last revised on January 19, 2024 at 14:12:29. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.