Showing changes from revision #12 to #13:
Added | Removed | Changed
This is a subentry of a reading guide to HTT.
In particular the following notions are important:
Left fibrations: These are the higher analogs of fibrations in groupoids.
Anodyne morphisms: These are morphisms possessing the left lifting property with respect to all Kan fibrations. Anodyne morphisms are precisely the acyclic cofibrations in the standard model structure on simplicial sets?.
The covariant model structure: This is a model structure on the over category . It is a model structure for left fibrations. It is functorial in . It is called covariant since by the -Grothendieck construction is associated to the category of covariant functors . There is also a notion of contravariant model structure where right fibrations is associated to .
The Joyal model structure: Precisely -categories are fibrant with respect to this model structure.
inner fibration and minimal fibration: These are used to develop a theory of n-categories.
cartesian fibration: These are higher analogs to Grothendieck fibrations (not necessarily in groupoids). These are defined with respect to cartesian morphisms.
categorical fibration?: These are the fibrations in the Joyal model structure on (also called model structure for quasi-categories): Morphisms of simplicial sets possessing the right lifting properties against acyclic cofibrations in this model structure. Here the cofibrations are the monomorphisms and the weak equivalences are called weak categorical equivalences. Categorical fibrations have no intrinsic meaning in -category theory. Fibrant objects in this model structure are precisely -categories.
For a general overview see model structure on simplicial sets and fibration of quasi-categories.
A morphism of simplicial sets is called
a Kan fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to every horn inclusion.
a trivial fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to every boundary inclusion .
a left fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to every horn inclusion except the right outer one.
a left fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to every horn inclusion except the left outer one.
a left fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to every inner horn inclusion.
left anodyne if it has the left lifing property with respect to every left fibration.
right anodyne if it has the left lifing property with respect to every right fibration.
inner anodyne if it has the left lifing property with respect to every inner fibration.
minimal fibration roughly said, when the morphism is determined by its values on the boundaries.
cartesian fibration
cocartesian fibration
categorical fibration
We have the following relations of kinds of fibrations where the arrows indicate implication (e.g. an acyclic fibration is a Kan fibration).
We have the following intuition in regard to these types of fibrations
Right fibrations are the -categorical analog of fibrations in groupoids.
Left fibrations are the -categorical analog of cofibrations in groupoids.
Cartesian fibrations are the -categorical analog of fibrations (not necessarily in groupoids).
(anodyne morphisms)
Every map of simplicial sets admits a factorization into an anodyne ((left anodyne, right anodyne, inner anodyne, a cofibration) followed by a Kan fibration (left fibration, right fibration, inner fibration, trivial fibration).
The theory of left fibrations and left anodyne morphisms is dual to that of right fibrations and right anodyne morphisms; i.e. if is a left fibration (left anodyne morphisms) iff the induced map right fibrations and right anodyne morphisms.
Left fibrations are analogs to fibrations in groupoids.
Let be a functor between categories. The is a fibrations in groupoids iff the induced map is a left fibration of simplicial sets.
Compare the following lemma with Proposition 2.1.3.1
Let be a left fibration of simplicial sets. The assignment
The aim of this section is to show that left fibrations exist in abundance.
The following remark follows from a theorem of Joyal (not displayed here).
(left fibrations) 1. The projection from the over category is a left fibration.
1.The property of being a left fibration is stable under forming functor categories.
Compare the following proposition with Lemma 2.1.1.4.
Let be a left fibration of simplicial sets. Then the following statements are equivalent
is a Kan fibration.
For every edge in , the map is an isomorphism in the homotopy category of spaces.
This section is a preparation for the Grothendieck consruction ( more precisely for the -Grothendieck construction) for -categories. See also Grothendieck construction in HTT.
Requisites are the discussion of model structures on simplicial sets HTT, A.2 and that of simplicially enriched categories HTT, A.3.
The covariant model structure is a ‘’relative model structure’‘ in that it is a model structure on an overcategory. In HTT the theory of model structures on over categories is developed only for the case of simplicial sets. This model is ‘’functorial in ’‘ in the sense that every morphism of simplicial sets induces a Quillen adjunction ; see Proposition 2.1.4.10.
For the following definition recall the definition of the right cone and the left cone of a simplicial set, where denotes the join of simplicial sets.
Let be a map of simplicial sets.
The simplicial set is called the left cone of .
Let be a map of simplicial sets.
Then there is a canonical monomorphism .
We hence regard as a simplicial subset. There is precisely one vertex of which does not belong to . We call this point the cone point of .
(the covariant model structure aka. model structure for left fibrations)
Let be a simplicial set . A morphism in is called a
(C) covariant cofibration if it is a monomorphism of simplicial sets.
(W) a covariant weak equivalence if the induced map
is a categorical weak equivalence.
(F) covariant fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to every map wich is both a covariant cofibration and a covariant equivalence.
Every left anodyne map is a covariant equivalence.
The covariant model structure determines a left proper, combinatorial model structure on
Every covariant fibration is a left fibration of simplicial sets
(the covariant model structure is functorial in )
For every map of simplicial sets we have a Quillen adjunction
with respect to the covariant model structure where is the postcomposition-with- functor and its right adjoint is given by .
There is also a contravariant model structure
Requisite: Theorem 2.4.6.1: Let be a simplicial set. Then is fibrant in the Joyal model structure iff is an -category.
The exists a left proper, combinatorial model structure on the category of simplicial sets such that
(C) Cofibrations are precisely monomorphisms
(W) A map is a categorical equivalence iff is an equivalence of simplicial categories. Where denotes the functor induced via Kan extension by the cosimplicial object , Definition 1.1.5.1, HTT.
here: (transclusion: give proof of Proposition 1.2.7.3
Let be a combinatorial monoidal model category. Let every object of be cofibrant. Let the collection of all weak equivalences in be stable under filtered colimits.
Then there exists a left proper, combinatorial model structure on such that:
(C) The class of cofibrations in is the smallest weakly saturated class of morphisms containing the set of morphisms defined in A.3.2.3. ( is some class of ‘’indicating morphisms’’).
(W) The weak equivalences in are those functors which are essentially surjective on the level of homotopy categories and such that for every .
Recall that equipped with the can model structure is an excellent model category.
Let be an excellent model category. Then:
An -enriched category is a fibrant object of iff it is locally fibrant: i.e. for all the hom object is fibrant.
Let be a -enriched functor where is a fibrant object of . Then is a fibration iff is a local fibration.
) here: give proof of Proposition 1.2.7.3
Every functor of classical categories induces an inner fibration
is a trivial fibration.
Every -category is categorial equivalenct to a minimal -category.
Let
denote a lifting problem. Then putative solutions of this lifting problem are called homotopic relative over if they are equivalent as objects in the fiber of the map
Equivalently are homotopic relative over if there is a map
such that
and is an equivalence in the -category for every vertex of .
Let be an inner fibration of simplicial sets. is called minimal inner fibration if for every pair of maps which are homotopic relative to over .
An -category is called minimal -category if is minimal.
(…)
Every -category is equivalent to a minimal -category.
Proposition 2.3.4.5: For a simplicial set the following statements are equivalent:
the unit is an isomorphism of simplicial sets.
There is small category and an isomorphism of simpliial sets .
is a 1-category.
Let be an -category. Let . Then the following statements are equivalent:
is an -category.
For every simplicial set and every pair of maps such that and are homotopic relative to , we have .
Let be an -category and let be a simplicial set. Then is an -category.
Let be an -category. Let .
There exists a simplicial set with the following universal mapping property: .
is an -category.
If is an -category, then the natural map is an isomorphism.
For every -category , composition with is an isomorphism of simplicial sets .
Let be an -category and let . The the following statements are equivalent:
There exists a minimal model such that is an -category.
There exists a categorical equivalence , where is an -category.
For every pair of objects , the mapping space is -truncated.
Let be a Kan complex. Then is is equivalent to an -category iff it is -truncated.
Let be an inner fibrations of simplicial sets. Let be an edge in . Then is called -cartesian if the induced map
is a trivial Kan fibration.
Every edge of a simplicial set is cartesian for an isomorphism.
Let be an inner fibration, let be the pullback of (which s then also an inner fibration). Then an edge is cartesian if ‘’its pullback’‘ is -cartesian.
(…)
Let be an inner fibration between -categories. Every identity morphism of (i.e. every degenerate edge of ) is -cartesian.
(left cancellation) Let be an inner fibration between simplicial sets. Let
Let be -cartesian. Then is -cartesian iff is -cartesian.
Let be a functor between simplicial categories. Let and be fibrant. Let for every pair of object be the associated map
be a Kan fibration. Then:
The associated map is an inner fibration between -categories.
A morphism in is -cartesian iff for every the diagram of simplicial sets
is a homotopy pullback.
Let be an inner fibration of simplicial sets. Let be an edge of . Let be a 3-simplex such that and . Let be a -cartesian edge such that . Then is -cartesian.
Let be a map of simplicial sets. Then is called a cartesian fibration if the following coditions are satisfied.
is an inner fibration.
Every edge of has a -cartesian lift.
Any isomorphism of simplicial sets is a cartesian fibration.
The class of cartesian fibrations is closed under base change.
A composition of cartesian fibrations is a cartesian fibration.