Showing changes from revision #14 to #15:
Added | Removed | Changed
This is a subentry of a reading guide to HTT.
(This is Joyal’s definition; it differs from A.2.1.1 in that Joyal requests to be finitely bicomplete.)
A model category is a category equipped with three distinguished classes of -morphisms: The classes , , of cofibrations, fibrations, and weak equivalences, respectively, satisfying the following axioms:
admits (small) limits and colimits.
The class of weak equivalences satisfies 2-out-of-3.
and are weak factorization systems.
The classes and is closed under retracts. (by weak factorization systems, Lemma 2, in joyal’s catlab)
The class is closed under retracts. (by model categories, Lemma 1, in joyal’s catlab)
Let be an object in a model category.
A cylinder object is defined to be a factorization of the codiagonal map for into a cofibration followed by a weak equivalence.
A path object is defined to be a factorization of the diagonal map for into a weak equivalence followed by a fibration .
Let be a model category. Let be a cofibrant object of . Let be a fibrant object of . Let be two parallel morphisms. Then the following conditions are equivalent.
The coproduct map factors through every cylinder object for .
The coproduct map factors through some cylinder object for .
The product map factors through every path object for .
The product map factors through some path object for .
(homotopy, homotopy category of a model category) Let be a model category.
(1) Two maps from a cofibrant object to a fibrant object satisfying the conditions of Proposition A.2.2.1 are called homotopic morphisms. Homotopy is an equivalence relation on .
(2) The homotopy category of is defined to have as objects the fibrant-cofibrant objects of . The hom objects are defined to be the set of equivalence classes of .
The following proposition says that a factorization of a cofibration between cofibrant objects which exists in the homotopy category of a model category can be lifted into the model category.
In every model category the class of fibrations is stable under pullback and the class of cofibrations is stable under pushout. In general weak equivalences do not have such properties. The following definition requests such.
A model category is called left proper if the pushout of a weak equivalence along a cofibration is a weak equivalence.
A model category is called right proper if the pullback of a weak equivalence along a fibration is a weak equivalence.
Any model category in which every object is cofibrant is left proper.
The push out along a cofibration of a weak equivalence between cofibrant objects is always a weak equivalence.
A Quillen adjunction is an appropriate notion of morphism between model categories.
An adjoint pair of functors is called a Quillen adjunction if the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
preserves cofibrations and acyclic cofibrations.
preserves fibrations and acyclic fibrations.
preserves cofibrations and preserves fibrations.
preserves acyclic cofibrations and preserves acyclic fibrations.
Let be a Quillen adjunction. Then
preserves weak equivalences between cofibrant objects.
preserves weak equivalences between fibrant objects.
(descent of a Quillen adjunction to an adjunction between the homotopy category)
Given a model category we obtain its homotopy category be passing to its full subcategory of cofibrant objects and the formally inverting the weak equivalences.
If is a Quillen adjunction induces a functor since preserves weak equivalences between cofibrant objects.
Analogously preserves weak equivalences between fibrant objects and we obtain from by passing to the category of fibrant objects of and formally invert the weak equivalences and hence induces a functor .
In total one can show that form an adjunction.
Abstracty one can obtain this result by Kan extension (this is also described at derived functor); however Quillen adjunction’s are introduced to present adjunctions between -categories and to obtain such a presentation in terms of Kan extension in general requires additional assumptions:
In more detail we wish to extend (for analogously) to a diagram
where is the universal morphism characterizing the homotopy category and similarly for .
This is accomplished by taking to be either the left () or right () Kan extension of along .
(characterization of derived functors, Quilen equivalence) Let be a Quillen adjunction of model categories. Then the following are equivalent:
The left derived functor is an equivalence of categories.
The right derived functor is an equivalence of categories.
For every cofibrant object and every fibrant object , a map is a weak equivalence iff the adjoint map is a weak equivalence.
is called Quillen equivalence if these conditions are satisfied.
(transclusion:
(weakly saturated class of morphisms)
Let be a category with all small colimits. A class of -morphisms is called a weakly saturated class if the following conditions are satisfied.
is closed under forming pushouts (along arbitrary -morphisms).
is closed under transfinite composition.
is closed under forming retracts.
)
A model category is called combinatorial model category if the following conditions are satisfied:
is presentable.
There exists a set of generating cofibrations such that the collection of all cofibrations is the smallest weakly saturated class of morphisms containing .
There exists a set of generating acyclic cofibrations such that the collection of all acyclic cofibrations is the smallest weakly saturated class of morphisms containing .
(perfect class) Let be a presentable category. A class of morphisms in is called perfect class if the following conditions are satisfied:
contaings all isomorpphisms.
satisfies 2-out-of-3
is stable under poset filtered colimits.
contains a small subset which generates under filtered colimits.
Let be a presentable category. Let be a class of -morphisms called called weak equivalences. Let be a small set of morphisms of called generating cofibrations satisfying:
(1) is a perfect class.
(2) For any diagram
where both sub squares are cocartesian, , and , the .
(3) A morphism in which has the right lifting property with respect to belongs to .
Then there exists a left proper, combinatorial model structure on defined by:
(C) A morphism is a cofibration if it belongs to the smallest weakly saturated class of morphisms generated by .
(W) A morphism is a weak equivalence if it belongs to .
(F) A morphism is a fibration if it has the right lifting property with respect to the class of acyclic cofibrations.
Let be a model category. Then arises via the construction of Proposition A.2.6.13 iff it is left proper, combinatorial and the class of weak equivalences in is stable under filtered colimits.
The standard model structure on the category of simplicial sets is defined by:
(W) A morphism is a weak equivalence if its geometric realization is a weak homotopy equivalence.
(C) Cofibrations are the monomorphisms.
(F) Fibrations are Kan fibrations.
(A.2.8.1, A.2.8.2)
If is a small category and is a combinatorial model category, then
The injective model structure on is a combinatorial model structure, determined by the strong cofibrations, weak equivalences, and projective fibrations.
The projective model structure on is a combinatorial model structure, determined by the weak cofibrations, weak equivalences, and injective fibrations.
If is moreover right proper resp. left proper, then is right proper resp. left proper.
A Quillen adjunction induces for every small category a Quillen adjunction with respect to either the injective- or the projective model structure.
is a Quillen equivalence iff is.
In other words: Forming the injective- resp. projective model structure is a functor.
(identity Quillen functor)
By Remark A.2.8.5 every projective cofibration is an injective cofibration and (dually) every injective fibration is a projective fibration. By definition the projective- and injective model structure have the same weak equivalences. It follows that the identity
is a Quillen equivalence between the injective- and the projective model structure.
Let be a functor between small categories. For a combinatorial model category let denote the functor given by precomposition with . By Kan extension we see that there are adjoints
and
(homotopy right Kan extension)
Let be a functor between small categories. The right derived functor functor of the functor assigning (which to is a the functor its right Kan adjoint extension to along ) is calledhomotopy right Kan extension.
(homotopy limit) Let denote the terminal category. Let be a combinatorial model category. Let denote a global element of . Let be a (note necessarily small) category. Let denote the unique functor to the terminal category. Let be a functor.
A natural transformation is called a homotopy limit of if exhibits as a homotopy Kan extension of .
Note that is the constant functor ‘’in ’’.
Let be a combinatorial model category, let be a functor between small categories. Let and be diagrams. A natural transformation exhibits G as a homotopy right Kan extension of if and only if, for each object , exhibits as a homotopy limit of the composite diagram
The following remark defines homotopy Kan extensions which in particular model Kan extensions between -categories:
Analog for homotopy colimits.