nLab generalized algebraic theory

Contents

Contents

Idea

A generalized algebraic theory (GAT, Cartmell 1978/86) consists of:

  1. An algebraic theory of sorts, which may itself be multi-sorted.

  2. A collection of operations, each having zero or more arguments and one result. Each nn-ary operation is also given with (n+1)(n+1)-many derived operations of the algebraic theory of sorts, all of the same arity, specifying the sort of each argument and the sort of the result.

  3. Equations between pairs of derived operations1 with the same arity and whose result sorts are provably equal in the algebraic theory of sorts (see example below).

To avoid confusion, this article will refer to the sorts of the algebraic theory of sorts as “supersorts” (this convention is not used in Cartmell’s paper).

Examples

The theory of categories is a GAT:

  1. Its algebraic theory of sorts is two-supersorted, with supersorts “Ob” and “Mor”, and one binary operation “Hom(-,+)” with arguments of supersort “Ob” and result of supersort “Mor”.

  2. Its operations include:

  • The unary operation id()id(-) with argument sort given by the derived operation xxx\mapsto x and result sort given by the derived operation xHom(x,x)x\mapsto Hom(x,x).

  • The binary operation comp(,+)comp(-,+) with first argument sort given by x,y,zHom(x,y)x,y,z\mapsto Hom(x,y) and second argument sort given by x,y,zHom(y,z)x,y,z\mapsto Hom(y,z) and result sort given by x,y,zHom(x,z)x,y,z\mapsto Hom(x,z)

  1. Its equations are
  • comp(id(a),f)=fcomp(id(a),f)=f where argument aa has sort x,yxx,y\mapsto x and argument ff has sort x,yHom(x,y)x,y\mapsto Hom(x,y)

  • comp(f,id(a))=fcomp(f,id(a))=f where argument aa has sort x,yyx,y\mapsto y and argument ff has sort x,yHom(x,y)x,y\mapsto Hom(x,y)

  • comp(f,comp(g,h))=comp(comp(f,g),h)comp(f,comp(g,h))=comp(comp(f,g),h) where argument ff has sort w,x,y,zHom(w,x)w,x,y,z\mapsto Hom(w,x), argument gg has sort w,x,y,zHom(x,y)w,x,y,z\mapsto Hom(x,y) and argument hh has sort w,x,y,zHom(y,z)w,x,y,z\mapsto Hom(y,z).

Note that this GAT has no equations imposed on the sort algebra.

One may also elect to include the following operations:

  • The unary operation dom()dom(-) with argument sort given by the derived operation x,yHom(x,y)x,y\mapsto Hom(x,y) and result sort given by the derived operation x,yxx,y\mapsto x

  • The unary operation cod()cod(-) with argument sort given by the derived operation x,yHom(x,y)x,y\mapsto Hom(x,y) and result sort given by the derived operation x,yyx,y\mapsto y

One can also directly axiomatize the theory of monoidal categories by adding:

  1. A 0-ary operation (constant) II of supersort “Ob” to the algebraic theory of sorts.

  2. A binary operation -\otimes - whose arguments and result are of supersort “Ob” to the algebraic theory of sorts.

  3. A fifth operation to the GAT having argument sort x 1,y 1,x 2,y 2Hom(x 1,y 1)x_1,y_1,x_2,y_2\mapsto Hom(x_1,y_1) and x 1,y 1,x 2,y 2Hom(x 2,y 2)x_1,y_1,x_2,y_2\mapsto Hom(x_2,y_2) and result sort x 1,y 1,x 2,y 2Hom(x 1x 2,y 1y 2)x_1,y_1,x_2,y_2\mapsto Hom(x_1\otimes x_2,y_1\otimes y_2)

  4. Operations for the left unitor (argument sort xxx\mapsto x, result sort xIxx\mapsto I\otimes x) and its inverse.

  5. Operations for the GAT for the right unitor (argument sort xxx\mapsto x, result sort xxIx\mapsto x\otimes I) and its inverse.

  6. Operations for the GAT for the associator (argument sort x,y,zx(yz)x,y,z\mapsto x\otimes(y\otimes z), result sort x,y,z(xy)zx,y,z\mapsto (x\otimes y)\otimes z) and its inverse.

  7. Quite a large number of additional equations corresponding to the pentagon and triangle diagrams, functoriality of the new fifth GAT operation, and inverse+naturality squares for remaining operations.

This GAT also has no equations on the sort algebra.

I suspsect that you can do strict monoidal categories too (though I haven’t worked it out completely) – but that definitely requires sort equations. – Adam

I think you can do multicategories too, but that requires infinitely many operations (in both the algebraic theory of sorts and the GAT itself) and infinitely many equations in the GAT. Even for finitary multicategories. – Adam

Finally, one can axiomatize the theory of categories with finite limits as a GAT. This GAT, however, requires equations on the algebra of sorts.

Relationship to Many-Sorted Algebraic Theories

A many-sorted algebraic theory is a GAT whose algebraic theory of sorts has no equations and no operations of arity greater than zero (i.e., has only constants).

Relationship to Essentially Algebraic Theories

Cartmell’s paper explains how for every GAT there is an essentially algebraic theory (EAT) with the same models and for every EAT there is a GAT with the same models. In this sense they are more or less equivalent in descriptive power.

Cartmell’s paper (in section 6) compares EAT’s to cartesian logic.

However (not in Cartmell’s paper), there is no notion in the world of EAT’s equivalent to a “GAT without sort equations”. This is relevant because it yields an interpretation result. Just as the theory of finite-limit categories is an EAT, and one can interpret any EAT in a finite-limit category, so too is the theory of monoidal categories a GAT without sort equations, and one can interpret any2 GAT without sort equations in a monoidal category.

Relationship to Enriched Categories

When one interprets the EAT of categories in a finite-limit category? VV, the result is a VV-internal category. When one interprets the GAT of categories in a monoidal category VV, the result is a VV-enriched category.

The theory of internal categories is an EAT (specifically, the theory for which a model is a category with a designated category internal to it). Likewise, the theory of enriched categories is a GAT without sort equations (specifically, the theory for which a model is a category with a category enriched in it).

Relationship to Type Theory

Type theories with type operators and polymorphism but without dependent types (such as System F ωF_\omega and the unbounded-rank polymorphic version of the Haskell type system) can represent any GAT without sort equations, encoding the sorts of the GAT as types and the operations of the algebraic theory of sorts as type operations. Type theories without dependent types generally enjoy better type inference properties than those with dependent types, making them practical as programming languages.

References


  1. An nn-ary derived operation of a GAT is defined in the same manner as a derived operation of a many-sorted algebra, except that it must also be given with (n+1)(n+1)-many derived operations of the algebraic theory of sorts. Just as in many-sorted algebras, composition of operations is permitted only when the sorts match; in the GAT case those sorts must match for any choice of sort-algebra-derived-operation arguments.

  2. The GAT of monoidal categories (without domdom and codcod) has a nice property: the argument and result sorts of compcomp are all the same, and we can get away with using the unit object II of the interpreting category for all sorts of supersort ObOb. I need to explain how to interpret GATs which lack this property — those which have more than one supersort with nontrivial sorts. Here’s a sketch: just as in the “nice” case the interpreting monoidal category VV will have an object for each sort of the GAT. Now construct a monoidal category KK with an object for each supersort and a morphism for each of the operations in the algebraic theory of sorts. If VV' is the subcategory of VV which does the interpretation, there ought to be a Grothendieck–Street Fibration of VV' over KK with the fibration functor sending each sort (VV-object) to its supersort (KK-object).

Last revised on July 20, 2022 at 14:30:51. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.