Ideals show up both in ring theory and in lattice theory. We recall both of these below and look at some slight generalizations.
A left ideal in a ring (or even rig) is a subset of (the underlying set of) such that:
A right ideal in is a subset such that:
A two-sided ideal in is a subset that is both a left and right ideal; that is:
This generalises to:
Notice that all three kinds of ideal are equivalent for a commutative ring.
This definition also makes sense for nonassociative rings (or rigs), with the left/right/two-sided coincidence in the commutative case.
In the case of a nonunital ring (or rig), if is being thought of as a module over some other ring , then it won't immediately follow that is a submodule of over , and so one usually includes that requirement as well:
in the case of left-modules, and similarly in the case of right modules or bimodules. (Technically, this should be distinguished in the terminology, say by calling an ideal of over or the like.) In particular, a (real or complex) Lie ideal of a Lie algebra is an ideal of over the real or complex field .
An ideal in a lattice (or even proset) is a subset of (the underlying set of) such that:
We can make this look more algebraic if is a (bounded) join-semilattice:
If is indeed a lattice, then we can make this look just like the ring version:
The concept of ideal is dual to that of filter. A subset of that satisfies the first two of the three axioms for an ideal in a proset is precisely a directed subset of ; notice that this is weaker than being a sub-join-semilattice even if is a lattice.
There are some common situations where these two kinds of ideal might seem to clash but fortunately do not:
A distributive lattice is both a lattice and a commutative rig; the two concepts of ideal are the same, as can be seen by comparing the definition for rigs to the last definition for lattices.
A Boolean algebra is a both a distributive lattice and a Boolean ring; again, the two concepts of ideal are the same (partly because the multiplication operators are the same, although there is still some checking to do regarding closure under addition).
On the other hand, every poset is a poset in an opposite way, and this does not give the same concept of ideal; an ideal in one is a filter in the opposite one. We are lucky that the convention for interpreting a Boolean ring as a lattice goes in the correct direction, or the two notions of ideal in a Boolean algebra would not match; or perhaps it is not a matter of luck, but the convention for which way to define ideals in a lattice was chosen precisely to match the conventions for Boolean algebras!
There is a notion of ideal in a monoid (or even semigroup), or more generally in a monoid object in any monoidal category , which generalises the notion of ideal in a ri(n)g or in a (semi)lattice. That is, if is Ab, then a monoid in is a ring; if is Ab Mon, then a monoid in is a rig; and a semilattice is a commutative idempotent monoid in Set. A left (right) ideal in a monoid (or semigroup) is a subset closed under multiplications with arbitrary elements in the semigroup from the left (right). See ideal in a monoid.
This generalizes all of the above notions of ideal except for ideals in prosets that are not (possibly unbounded) join-semilattices.
More generally still, passing from monoids to their many-object version and from prosets to their many-morphism version, a right ideal or sieve in a category is a subcategory closed under precomposition with morphisms from the entire category, and a cosieve or left ideal is the dual notion closed under postcompositions with morphisms in the entire category. See sieve.
In ringoids (small additive categories) and additive categories in general, a left/right/2-sided ideal is just the ideal (sieve/cosieve) in the sense of categories which is also closed under group operations in hom groups.
Ideals form complete lattices where arbitrary meets are given by set-theoretic intersection. In other words, ideals form a Moore collection of subsets of if is a rig, or of if is a lattice. This implies we have an ideal generated by any subset: the intersection of all ideals containing the subset. A subset that generates a given ideal may be called a subbase of ; then is a base if every element of is a multiple (in a rig) or a predecessor (in an order) of some element of . (In particular, every singleton subset is a base of its generated ideal.) See also filter base and dualize for more about bases and subbases of ideals in lattices and other posets.
Certain kinds of ideals are often characterized by the roles they play in ideal lattices, or in terms of the Moore closure operator. Some examples follow.
The top element of an ideal lattice is called the improper ideal. That is to say, an ideal is the improper ideal if for every (which follows if for the case of rigs, or for the case of bounded lattices). An ideal is proper if it is not the improper ideal: if there exists an element such that . So in a rig, is proper iff ; in a (bounded) lattice, is proper iff .
An ideal is a maximal ideal if it is maximal among proper ideals. A maximal ideal in a rig (including in a distributive lattice, but not in every lattice) is necessarily prime; conversely, a prime ideal in a Boolean algebra is necessarily maximal.
An ideal is a principal ideal if it is generated by a singleton. This means there exists an element such that is a multiple of (in a rig) or (in an ordered set) whenever ; we say that is generated by . Thus every element generates a unique principal ideal, the set of all left/right/two-sided multiples of (, , or if we are talking about left/right/two-sided ideals in a rig) or the downset of (in an an order). Clearly, every ideal is a join over all the principal ideals generated by the elements of .
As discussed at ideals in a monoid, there is for two-sided ideals an operation of ideal multiplication, making the ideal lattice a quantale (cf. Day convolution). Namely, if are ideals, then their product is the ideal generated by all products with in the case of rigs. Similarly, in the case of lattices, we could define to be the ideal generated by all meets – but in this case the result is the same as . In any case, we say that a proper ideal is prime if for any ideals , the condition implies or . In order theory, the term ‘prime ideal’ is usually used for a strongly irreducible ideal, since the two are equivalent for prosets.
An (left, right, or two-sided) ideal is irreducible if it is proper and, whenever it is written as the intersection of two ideals (of the same kind) , then at least one of and equals . If we replace equality here by containment, then we get something more analogous to the definition of prime ideal, called a strongly irreducible ideal. (Indeed, for prosets, prime ideals and strongly irreducible ideals are the same.) In general, prime ideals are strongly irreducible, and strongly irreducible ideals are irreducible, but the converses fail. An ideal is completely irreducible if whenever is an intersection of any (possibly infinite) collection of ideals, is equal to at least one of them. (This is not analogous to completely prime ideals.)
An ideal is a nil ideal if for every , there is an with . That is, every element of the ideal is nilpotent. If on the other hand, there is an , such that for every , , the ideal is called nilpotent.
A maximal ideal is prime.
Because the ideal lattice is a quantale, multiplication of ideals distributes over ideal joins. Suppose for two ideals . If neither is contained in , then (the improper ideal) since is maximal. Then
where all four summands are contained in ( by supposition, and the other containments hold since is an ideal). Thus their join is contained in , so we have proved , contradiction.
That every ideal is contained in a prime ideal is a prime ideal theorem; that every ideal is contained in a maximal ideal is a maximal ideal theorem.
Last revised on October 1, 2024 at 19:40:16. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.