Let be a field, and a monic polynomial of degree . A splitting field for is a field extension such that, regarding as a polynomial in by applying the map
the polynomial factors or “splits” as a product of linear factors (possibly repeated):
with all the roots lying in , and the smallest subfield of containing and these roots is itself (so that the roots generate : .
More generally, given a set of monic polynomials, an extension field for which each splits over , and which as a field is generated over by the set of accompanying roots, is called a splitting field for .
The existence of a splitting field for a single polynomial can be proven by induction on . As is a unique factorization domain, is a product of irreducible polynomials . The ideal is maximal and so is an finite field extension of where the coset is a root of , and . Then has degree , and thus has a splitting field by induction, whence splits as in , and then in . Finally we have the generation condition:
What is not clear from this construction is that splitting fields are unique (up to isomorphism). This is the case however:
Splitting fields of a polynomial are unique up to (non-unique) isomorphism.
(After Conrad.) Suppose and are two splitting fields of a polynomial . The tensor product is a coproduct of and in the category of commutative algebras over ; let and be the coproduct injections. Observe that as a -algebra, is generated by the together with the .
Now let be any maximal ideal of (note that is finite-dimensional over , so the existence of does not involve any choice principles), and consider the composite
As is the case for any homomorphism between fields, this composite is an injective map. Moreover, letting denote the coset and the coset , the polynomial splits over the field as
and so by unique factorization of polynomials, for each there is a with . This means the exhaust the generators of . In other words, is also surjective and provides an isomorphism . By symmetry we also have an isomorphism , and thus .
A splitting field for a finite set of polynomials is just a splitting field of the product .
Now let be an arbitrary set of monic polynomials. For each , let denote the degree of , and let us introduce a set of indeterminates . Let be the coproduct , and form the polynomial algebra . For each let us write
for some elements . We claim that the set of all with ranging over generates a proper ideal in . For given an -linear combination with , where is associated with a polynomial , let be the splitting field of , and define a homomorphism that sends distinct elements of the form to distinct roots of , and otherwise sends with to . Then is sent to in , hence cannot be .
Let be a prime ideal containing the ideal generated by ; the existence of such is guaranteed under the ultrafilter principle. The ring is an integral domain; by construction every splits over and the roots of such generate as a -algebra. These roots thus generate its field of fractions as a field and is therefore a splitting field for .
In particular, taking to be the set of all monic polynomials in , this gives an efficient construction of the algebraic closure of that invokes not the full strength of the axiom of choice (in the form of Zorn's lemma), but only of the weaker ultrafilter principle.
Any two splitting fields of a given set of polynomials are isomorphic.
Again we prove this only under the assumption of the ultrafilter principle, and not under the assumption of full axiom of choice.
(After Caicedo.) Let be splitting fields for ; without loss of generality we may suppose is closed under multiplication of polynomials. For let denote the corresponding subfields obtained by adjoining all roots of that occur in to the ground field . Any isomorphism restricts to an isomorphism . Notice that the form a directed system of fields, with an inclusion morphism if divides , and is the colimit of the over this directed system. We are required to show that the set of isomorphisms is nonempty; we have restriction maps which exhibit as the inverse limit of over the corresponding system, with transition maps for also given by restriction. So we are required to show that this inverse limit is inhabited.
By Theorem , the set of isomorphisms is inhabited, and it is also finite (being a torsor of the group which has cardinality at most where is the number of roots). It can then be proven from the ultrafilter theorem that is nonempty; see here for a proof. Similarly, the subset
is also nonempty, as is any finite intersection of such subsets (which actually is another , by considering the product of ‘s and ’s).
Now topologized as a product of finite discrete spaces is a compact Hausdorff space; this version of the Tychonoff theorem also follows from the ultrafilter theorem. We conclude from compactness that the full intersection is inhabited. But this intersection is just the inverse limit which is , which concludes the proof.
An alternative proof based on a similar pattern of reasoning, but more explicitly in the language of model theory and the compactness theorem, was given by Joel David Hamkins, in an answer following Caicedo’s at MathOverflow.
Bernhard Banaschewski, Algebraic closure without choice, Mathematical Logic Quarterly, Vol. 38 Issue 1 (1992), 383–385. (doi: 10.1002/malq.19920380136, paywall)
Keith Conrad, Isomorphisms of Splitting Fields, Galois theory notes [pdf]
Andres Caicedo Is the statement that every field has an algebraic closure known to be equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma?, URL (version: 2010-11-19): http://mathoverflow.net/q/46568
Joel David Hamkins, Is the statement that every field has an algebraic closure known to be equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma?, URL (version: 2010-11-20): http://mathoverflow.net/q/46729
Last revised on October 25, 2023 at 12:15:31. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.