symmetric monoidal (∞,1)-category of spectra
A field is algebraically closed if every non-constant polynomial (with one variable and coefficients from ) has a root in . It follows that every polynomial of degree can be factored uniquely (up to permutation of the factors) as
where and the are elements of .
An algebraic closure of an arbitrary field is an algebraically closed field equipped with a field homomorphism (necessarily an injection) such that is an algebraic extension of (which means that every element of is the root of some non-zero polynomial with coefficients only from ). For example, is an algebraic closure of . An algebraic closure of can also be described as a maximal algebraic extension of . The axiom of choice proves the existence of for any field , as well as its uniqueness up to isomorphism over . (See splitting field for a more refined result.) However, note that need not be unique up to unique isomorphism, so it's not really appropriate to speak of the algebraic closure of . For example, complex conjugation is a nontrivial automorphism of over .
Without choice, the existence and uniqueness of algebraic closures may fail; see Chow06, Banaschewski92, Richman00.
Even with choice, algebraic closure is not functorial in any reasonable sense. For example, it is very easy to demonstrate that there is no algebraic closure functor that renders the inclusion natural:
Supposing there were such an algebraic closure functor , consider its application to the (equalizer) diagram
We would have a commutative naturality diagram (meaning serially commutative on the right)
where serial commutativity of the right square(s) forces , but functoriality applied to the equation on the top forces (no matter which isomorphism is taken to be, or ).
Thus, any two algebraic closures are isomorphic, but not naturally so.
Putting aside the concerns of constructive mathematics, and freely adopting the principle of the excluded middle and the axiom of choice, algebraically closed fields are characterized (up to non-unique isomorphism) by just two cardinal invariants:
Two algebraically closed fields are isomorphic iff they have the same characteristic (the nonnegative generator of the kernel of the unique ring map ) and the same transcendence degree (the cardinality of any maximal set of algebraically independent elements).
In outline, the proof is simple in structure. The “only if” statement is clear, provided we allow that transcendence degree is well-defined. For the “if” statement, contains a subring isomorphic to where is a transcendence basis, and similarly contains a subring isomorphic to . By hypothesis, there is a bijection , which extends uniquely to an isomorphism of integral domains , which extends uniquely to an isomorphism of their fields of fractions . Then are algebraic closures of these fields, and one applies a theorem that an isomorphism of fields can be extended to an isomorphism of their algebraic closures.
The full details of such a proof carry some themes important in model theory:
There is a notion of algebraic closure of a subset,
There are prime models (algebraic closure of prime field ),
There are notions of independence and basis, and well-defined degree or dimension,
There are extensions of isomorphisms of independent sets to isomorphisms of their algebraic closures.
Perhaps the most subtle in the list is the notion of independence and well-definedness of (transcendence) degree, which notably involves verification of the Steinitz exchange axiom:
Let be an algebraically closed field, and let be the operator that takes a subset to the smallest algebraically closed subfield that contains . Then is a pregeometry.
For the moment, please consult Jacobson, Basic Algebra II, Theorem 8.34. This may be expanded upon a little later.
Well-definedness of transcendence degree then follows from abstract considerations of pregeometries; see this result.
The fundamental theorem of algebra is, classically, the statement that the complex numbers form an algebraically closed field .
Arguably, this theorem is not entirely algebraic; the algebraic portion is that is algebraically closed whenever is a real-closed field. Unusually, this algebraic portion is not (as stated) valid in constructive mathematics, while the analytic result (that the real numbers form a real closed field ) is constructively valid with the usual definitions.
The algebraic closure of the rational numbers is the algebraic numbers.
The algebraic closure of a field is the splitting field of the set of all monic polynomials over . Thus for relevant material, see
Algebraic closure of Q, a thread on FOM started by Timothy Chow;
be sure to check for improperly replied posts with the same subject in that and the next two months
Bernhard Banaschewski, Algebraic closure without choice, Mathematical Logic Quarterly, Volume 38, Issue 1, 1992, Pages 383-385, [doi:10.1002/malq.19920380136]
Fred Richman, The fundamental theorem of algebra: a constructive development without choice, Pacific Journal of Mathematics 196 1 (2000) 213–230 [doi:10.2140/pjm.2000.196.213, pdf]
Wim Ruitenberg, Constructing Roots of Polynomials over the Complex Numbers, Computational Aspects of Lie Group Representations and Related Topics, CWI Tract, Vol. 84, Centre for Mathematics and Computer Science, Amsterdam, 1991, pp. 107–128. (pdf)
Last revised on February 9, 2024 at 23:39:26. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.