In material set theory as a foundation of mathematics, the axiom of pairing is an important axiom needed to get the foundations off the ground (to mix metaphors). It states that pair sets exist.
The axiom of pairing (or axiom of pairs) states the following:
Axiom of pairing: If and are (material) sets, then there exists a set such that and .
Using the axiom of separation (bounded separation is enough), we can prove the existence of a particular set such that and are the only members of . Using the axiom of extensionality, we can then prove that this set is unique; it is usually denoted and called the pair set of and . Note that may also be denoted simply .
One could also assume that the material set theory has a primitive binary operation which takes of a material set and and returns a material set . Then the axiom of pairing becomes
Axiom of pairing: If and are (material) sets, then and .
The axiom of unordered pairing (or axiom of unordered pairs) states the following:
Axiom of unordered pairing: If and are (material) sets, then there exists a set such that and and for all sets , implies that or .
Using the axiom of extensionality, we can then prove that this set is unique; it is usually denoted and called the pair set of and . Note that may also be denoted simply .
One could also assume that the material set theory has a primitive binary operation which takes of a material set and and returns a material set . Then the axiom of pairing becomes
Axiom of unordered pairing: If and are (material) sets, then , , and for all sets , implies that or .
Let us assume that the material set theory has a primitive binary operation which takes of a material set and and returns a material set .
The axiom of ordered pairing (or axiom of ordered pairs) states the following:
Axiom of ordered pairing: If and are (material) sets, then , , and for all sets and , if and only if and .
In set theories where sets and elements are not the same thing, pairing becomes an operation on both the sets and the elements. One has to add a primitive ternary relation which says that is the Cartesian product of and , as well as primitive quaternary relations and which says that element is the left element of the pair and element is the right element of the pair , and the following axiom:
Axiom of ordered pairing: If and are sets, then there exists a set such that and for every object and , and implies that there exists an object such that , , and
is usually denoted and called the Cartesian product of and , while is usually denoted and called the ordered pair of and .
In dependent type theory, it is possible to define a Tarski universe of pure sets which behaves as a material set theory. The universal type family of the Tarski universe is given by the type family . The axiom of pairing is given by the following inference rule:
The axiom of pairing is the binary part of a binary/nullary pair whose nullary part is the axiom stating the existence of the empty set. We can use these axioms and the axiom of union to prove every instance of the following axiom (or rather theorem) schema of finite sets:
If are sets, then there exists a set such that .
Again, we can prove the existence of specific such that are the only members of and prove that this is unique; it is denoted and is called the finite set consisting of .
Note that this is a schema, with one instance for every (metalogical) natural number. Within axiomatic set theory, this is very different from the single statement that begins with a universal quantification over the (internal) set of natural numbers. In particular, each instance of this schema can be stated and proved without the axiom of infinity. Of course, there is one proof for each natural number.
Note that these ‘finite sets’ are precisely the Kuratowski-finite sets in a constructive treatment.
In the Lab, the term ‘pairing’ usually refers to ordered pairs.
For the axiom of ordered pairing see:
Last revised on February 28, 2024 at 03:14:48. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.