The term ‘infinitesimal’ means the same as ‘infinitely small in absolute value’; in Latin, it literally means ‘infinity-eth’ and should be interpreted in the sense of a fraction. In the ordinary analysis of real numbers, the only infinitesimal number is zero. However, the basic intuitions of calculus since its beginnings have dealt with infinitely small (and sometimes also infinitely large) numbers. There are several different ways to develop a rigorous theory that includes infinitesimal numbers.
Briefly we recall the definition of what makes a number infinitesimal, which we give in some generality.
Let be a cancellative commutative monoid equipped with a strict weak order such that does not hold for any element of ; that is, the additive identity is a bottom element with respect to the partial order induced by the negation of the strict weak order, and an element such that . Let be a cancellative commutative monoid equipped with a function , thought of as a measure of absolute value, such that . For example, could consist of the real numbers with the nonnegative real numbers; similarly, we may consider the natural numbers, the complex numbers, the cardinal numbers, and many other familiar examples of numbers. (In these examples, and satisfy additional compatibility properties with respect to the cancellative commutative monoids and , but these do not seem to enter into the definition. Conversely, we do not use the full cancellative commutative monoid structure of and , so the definition should work in even greater generality.)
An element of is infinitesimal if the sum of elements of has absolute value less than : for every natural number . The sum of elements of an element in a cancellative commutative monoid always exists, since every monoid is power-associative.
According to this definition, is always infinitesimal. Traditionally, one adds to the definition the requirement that , but this leads to a less useful notion of the space of all infinitesimals. We allow to be infinitesimal for some of the same reasons that we allow it to be a natural number. (Although the argument is even stronger here, since it’s always decidable whether a given natural number is zero, but it may not be decidable whether a given infinitesimal is zero. This is especially important in synthetic differential geometry, where the logic is unavoidably constructive.)
In the usual systems of numbers (real, natural, complex, cardinal, etc), is the only infinitesimal number. So the interesting question is how to get other infinitesimals.
The simplest way to add an infinitesimal to an ordered ring (or rig) is freely. For example, if we start with the field of real numbers, then form the polynomial ring , we may make (and every nonconstant polynomial) infinitesimal by defining for every positive real number and generating the rest of by requiring that be an ordered ring. (This amounts to defining to mean that for sufficiently small positive values of .)
If you want a field, then form the field of fractions of , which is the field of rational functions. This is a very commonly known example, although it is more usual to make infinitely large (so that is infinitesimal).
Similarly, one can use polynomials to define infinitesimal versions of complex numbers, cardinal numbers, etc.
The downside of this approach is that the resulting infinitesimal numbers will be subject only to those operations that apply to the category in which one forms the free construction. For example, there is no way to apply transcendental functions to infinitesimals with this approach. Presumably that could be fixed by working with -rings, but no algebraic theory covers everything that can be done with real numbers (or whatever numbers you start with).
Alternatively, one could formally complete the polynomial ring to get the ring of formal power series . This results in a local integral domain if is a field. In the case that is an Archimedean ordered field, then is an Archimedean ordered local integral domain; and if is sequentially Cauchy complete, this allows for any analytic function to be defined on . The infinitesimals in are the formal power series whose leading 0th-power term is equal to zero, or equivalently, the product of and a formal power series.
Instead of working with free infinitesimals, we could also work with nilpotent infintiesimals. This requires working in an Archimedean ordered Artinian local -algebras. Since these are not ordered fields, the strict weak order is not a strict total order, the preorder is not a partial order, and the apartness relation is not tight. There is an equivalence relation which says that is approximately equal to , and is defined by if and only if the difference is a zero divisor.
Given an Archimedean ordered Artinian local -algebra , since is a local ring, the quotient of by its ideal of non-invertible elements is the real numbers , and the canonical function used in defining the quotient ring is the function which takes a number to its purely real component . Since is an ordered -algebra, there is a strictly monotone ring homomorphism . A number is purely real if , and a number is purely infinitesimal if it is in the ideal of zero divisors , the fiber of at the real number . Zero is the only number in which is both purely real and purely infinitesimal.
The advantage of working with nilpotent infinitesimals is that the ring homomorphism preserves smooth functions: given a natural number and a purely infinitesimal number such that , then for every smooth function , there is a function such that for all real numbers , and
If we restrict to Archimedean ordered local Artinian -algebras where every element of the nilradical is a nilsquare element, where for all , , then the ring homomorphism preserves differentiable functions; for every differentiable function , there is a function such that for all real numbers and nilpotent elements , and
This allows us to define certain differentiable functions on the real numbers, such as the exponential function, the sine function, and the cosine function, through its property as solutions to systems of first-order ordinary differential equations, without having to define the notion of limit of a sequence, series, integral, and prove the fundamental theorem of calculus and/or convergence of Taylor series.
One could also work with partial functions instead of functions. Given a predicate on the real numbers , let denote the set of all elements in for which holds. A partial function is equivalently a function for any such predicate and set .
A function is smooth at a subset with injection if it has a function with for all , such that for all Archimedean ordered Artinian local -algebras with ring homomorphism , natural numbers , and purely infinitesimal elements such that
Special cases include being smooth at an element , which is the same as being smooth at the singleton subset , and being smooth which is the same as being smooth at the improper subset of .
This approach is used in synthetic differential geometry, where one adds additional axioms to the foundations stating that the only functions on are the smooth functions.
If the point is to do with infinitesimal numbers everything that we can do with ordinary numbers, then why not use high-powered logic to do this for us? That is the approach taken by Abraham Robinson in nonstandard analysis.
Nonstandard analysis can be applied to mathematics as a whole, so it treats complex numbers, cardinal numbers, and the rest all together.
…
Another approach is to focus only on what we want to do with infinitesimals in a particular field. Since infinitesimals were used to do calculus, then let's just do calculus. We can take as axiomatic the familiar properties of smooth functions used in calculus, including the ways these were applied to infinitesimals before analysis was made rigorous (by modern standards) in the 19th century. This is the approach taken by Bill Lawvere and others in synthetic differential geometry.
…
The surreal numbers have infinitesimals, and include both the real numbers and the ordinal numbers. But they are not much good for ordinary calculus, although there are some indications that they might have applications in asymptotics.
There is also an interpretation of pre-Cauchy calculus in which infinitesimals are interpreted as infinite sequences that converge to . I don't know much about this.
All the infinitesimals appearing in nonstandard analysis are invertible, since the hyperreal numbers form a field. (This is also true for all the surreal infinitesimals.) By contrast, most of the infinitesimals appearing in synthetic differential geometry are nilpotent, and hence not invertible. However, there are some models that do contain invertible infinitesimals, and hence also ‘infinite’ numbers as their inverses (see smooth natural number). Two such models are the smooth toposes called and in
These toposes are related to the smooth topos called there, which has nilpotent but no invertible infinitesimals, by a transfer theorem (chapter VII, section 4) valid for a certain class of coherent formulas. Additionally, the ‘object of nonstandard smooth natural numbers’ in these toposes is defined by an ‘algebra of unbounded sequences’, similar in spirit to the unbounded sequences which represent infinitely large numbers in nonstandard analysis. However, it is not clear whether any more precise comparison can be made.
ring with infinitesimals | function |
---|---|
dual numbers | differentiable function |
Weil ring | smooth function |
power series ring | analytic function |
article in the English Wikipedia for etymology
Hermann Cohen, Das Prinzip der Infinitesimal-Methode und seine Geschichte , Berlin 1883. (html)
Mikhail Katz, David Sherry, Leibniz’s Infinitesimals: Their Fictionality, Their Modern Implementations, And Their Foes From Berkeley To Russell And Beyond, D. Erkenn (2013) 78: 571 (arXiv:1205.0174, doi:10.1007/s10670-012-9370-y)
(on Gottfried Leibniz‘s concept of infinitesimals)
Last revised on December 25, 2023 at 22:40:29. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.