nLab natural transformation (discussion)

Contents

Contents

Discussion 2.0

Eric: This discussion began when I asked the following questions:

Eric: For some reason, I always thought a natural transformation was a more general map between functors α:FG\alpha:F\Rightarrow G, where

F:ABandG:CD.F:A\to B\quad\text{and}\quad G:C\to D.

Then α(F):CD\alpha(F):C\to D is a functor and we’d probably also want 2-component functors α C:AC\alpha_C:A\to C and α D:BD\alpha_D:B\to D such that the following diagram commutes

A F B α C α α D C G D \array{ A & \stackrel{F}{\to} & B \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_C}}\downarrow &\mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha}}\Downarrow & \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_D}} \\ C & \stackrel{G}{\to} & D }

If this is not a natural transformation, is there another name for it?

When A=CA = C and B=DB = D, this should coincide with the usual definition. If so, why don’t we define natural transformation in this more general way? It seems more “natural” to me.

Eric: I hope to pick up where we left off because I was making some progress understanding some of this stuff.

I like the above concept, but I’m still trying to find the right label for it. The standard definition of natural transformation involves a map between functors (sharing the same domain and codomain) together with component morphisms. What I’m trying to describe is a map between functors (not necessarily with the same domain and codomain) together with component functors.

This seems to be a natural thing to do, especially when thinking of functors as maps between morphisms, together with component morphisms, as put forward at functor (discussion).

From there, it is a skip away from thinking of morphisms as maps between objects together with component objects. Hmmm…

The whole thing just wants to bumped up incrementally in dimension.

Functor Revisited

Definition (Experimental)

Given categories AA, BB and inclusion maps i A:AABi_A:A\to A\sqcup B, i B:BABi_B:B\to A\sqcup B, a functor is a map F:ABF:A\to B together with component morphisms α x:i A(x)i BF(x)\alpha_x:i_A(x)\to i_B\circ F(x) and α y:i A(y)i BF(y)\alpha_y:i_A(y)\to i_B\circ F(y) for any morphism f:xyf:x\to y in AA such that the following diagram commutes:

i A(x) i A(f) i A(y) α x F α y i BF(x) i BF(f) i BF(y) \array{ i_A(x) & \stackrel{i_A(f)}{\to} & i_A(y) \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_x}}\downarrow &\mathllap{F}\Downarrow & \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_y}} \\ i_B\circ F(x) & \stackrel{i_B\circ F(f)}{\to} & i_B\circ F(y) }

For a less cluttered diagram, we can omit the obvious inclusion maps and look at

x f y α x F α y F(x) F(f) F(y) \array{ x & \stackrel{f}{\to} & y \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_x}}\downarrow &\mathllap{F}\Downarrow & \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_y}} \\ F(x) & \stackrel{F(f)}{\to} & F(y) }

Discussion 1.0

Eric: For some reason, I always thought a natural transformation was a more general map between functors α:FG\alpha:F\Rightarrow G, where

F:ABandG:CD.F:A\to B\quad\text{and}\quad G:C\to D.

Then α(F):CD\alpha(F):C\to D is a functor and we’d probably also want 2-component functors α C:AC\alpha_C:A\to C and α D:BD\alpha_D:B\to D such that the following diagram commutes

A F B α C α α D C G D \array{ A & \stackrel{F}{\to} & B \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_C}}\downarrow &\mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha}}\Downarrow & \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_D}} \\ C & \stackrel{G}{\to} & D }

If this is not a natural transformation, is there another name for it?

When A=CA = C and B=DB = D, this should coincide with the usual definition. If so, why don’t we define natural transformation in this more general way? It seems more “natural” to me.

Urs Schreiber: I suppose your 2-arrow in the middle labeled α\alpha is supposed to be a natural transformation (in the standard sense)?

Then this is a square in the 2-category of categories. Such squares appear in turn as the components of lax natural transformations of 2-functors into Cat.

Eric: Thanks. I was hesitant to put that 2-arrow in there. I’m still learning this stuff and am on shaky ground. But no. That 2-arrow is not supposed to be a natural transformation in the traditional sense because it is not a map between functors with the same domain and codomain. It is tempting to say we might want α DFα CG\alpha_D\circ F\Rightarrow\alpha_C\circ G to be a natural transformation in the traditional sense though.

Toby: That arrow certainly looks to me like a 22-arrow from α DF\alpha_D\circ F to α CG\alpha_C\circ G. Unless it has no particular meaning and is just labelling the entire square as α:FG\alpha\colon F \Rightarrow G. In any case, there is the question of what, if anything, goes between α DF\alpha_D\circ F and α CG\alpha_C\circ G. If nothing, then I would call such a thing a square of functors. If something more interesting, see my answer at Natural Transformation (which I saw first).

Todd: Here’s one way of considering how the standard notion of natural transformation is the “right” one. Just as in topology we would like to consider the “space of all continuous maps XYX \to Y” from one space to another as a topological space, and the right notion of topology so we get an appropriate universal property, we want the same thing here. So the term analogous to “space” is “category”, the term analogous to “continuous map” is “functor”, and the term analogous to “space of all continuous maps from one space to another” or “function space” is “category of all functors from one category to another” or “functor category”. And there should be a universal property which gives the right such category.

In the end, if D CD^C denotes the functor category, the universal property provides an equivalence between functors XD CX \to D^C and functors X×CDX \times C \to D. Pursuing this, let’s figure out what morphisms in D CD^C should look like. In an ordinary category YY, a morphism in YY corresponds to a functor 2Y\mathbf{2} \to Y, where 2\mathbf{2} is a category with two objects 0,10, 1 and exactly one nonidentity arrow 010 \to 1. So morphisms in D CD^C should correspond to functors 2D C\mathbf{2} \to D^C. And the universal property says these are equivalent to functors 2×CD\mathbf{2} \times C \to D. Now: if you carefully work through what functors of that form give you, you get precisely the notion of natural transformation. This is an exercise well worth working out.

This is how you know the notion of natural transformation is morally the “right” one.

Urs Schreiber: I added above a subsection on this characterization in terms of the cartesian closed monoidal structure on CatCat.

Eric: I think I got it.

Given two functors F:ABF:A\to B and G:CDG:C\to D, let α:FG\alpha:F\Rightarrow G together with component functors α C:AC\alpha_C:A\to C and α D:BD\alpha_D:B\to D be a map such that

α DFGα C\alpha_D\circ F\Rightarrow G\circ\alpha_C

is a natural transformation (in the standard sense). Does this guy have a name?

The reason why I bring this up is that I do not like bigons. Bigons are not a good shape for doing computational geometry, geometric realization, etc. So before I could finally grok what a cone was, I had to draw a bunch of diagrams. These diagrams were bigons. Yucky!

Thanks Todd. That was a valiant effort, but didn’t manage to convince me (I have a thick skull!). I still like this more general definition. Given topological spaces W,X,Y,ZW,X,Y,Z, we could also be interested in studying spaces (WX)(YZ)(W\to X)\Rightarrow (Y\to Z). What you described would then be a special case where W=YW=Y and X=ZX=Z.

Here is my attempt to formalize an alternative definition:


Definition

Given categories AA,BB,CC,DD and functors F:ABF:A\to B,G:CDG:C\to D a natural transformation α:FG\alpha:F \Rightarrow G

A F B α C α α D C G D \array{ A & \stackrel{F}{\to} & B \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_C}}\downarrow &\mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha}}\Downarrow & \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_D}} \\ C & \stackrel{G}{\to} & D }

assigns functors α C:AC\alpha_C:A\to C and α D:BD\alpha_D:B\to D called component functors and for any morphism f:xyf:x\to y in AA assigns morphisms α x:α DF(x)Gα C(x)\alpha_x:\alpha_D\circ F(x)\to G\circ\alpha_C(x) and α y:α DF(y)Gα C(y)\alpha_y:\alpha_D\circ F(y)\to G\circ\alpha_C(y) in DD called component morphisms such that the following diagram commutes in DD:

α DF(x) α DF(f) α DF(y) α x α y Gα C(x) Gα C(f) Gα C(y) \array{ \alpha_D\circ F(x) & \stackrel{\alpha_D\circ F(f)}{\to} & \alpha_D\circ F(y) \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_x}}\downarrow && \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_y}} \\ G\circ\alpha_C(x) & \stackrel{G\circ\alpha_C(f)}{\to} & G\circ\alpha_C(y) }

Again, this reduces to the traditional definition when α C\alpha_C and α D\alpha_D are identity functors. What do you think? If this doesn’t already have a name (it probably does), what would be a good name for it?

Toby: This is exactly what I was talking about at Natural Transformation. I would call it a lax commutative square of functors.

Eric: Ok, but this seems to be “rotated 45 45^\circ” relative to what you said there. Here α:FG\alpha:F\Rightarrow G is a map between functors (not composites functors) with distinct domains and codomains having component functors α C\alpha_C, α D\alpha_D and component morphisms α x\alpha_x, α y\alpha_y. I’m trying to emphasize the map α:FG\alpha:F\Rightarrow G. Now, I’m trying to think about how I might reinterpret functors in this way so that we can iterate the process to higher degrees.

Urs: no, the α\alpha the way you defined it is a transformation between the composite functors: it is precisely a natural transformation from α DF\alpha_D \circ F to Gα CG \circ \alpha_C

Toby: You are right that it is rotated conceptually, but what I wrote there was also supposed to be rotated conceptually. The thing itself is indifferent to being from FF to GG, but once you declare (conceptually) that it is to be something from FF to GG, then what you have is a morphism in an arrow 22-category, as I wrote there.

Eric: Thanks Toby. Here is a prepared remark with a comment below:


I wrote the definition down intentionally so that the composite is a natural transformation, but I hope I can convince you that α:FG\alpha:F\Rightarrow G is not a natural transformation because the domains and codomains of FF and GG do not coincide (which they must to be a standard natural transformation). I’ll call it something else then. How about “sheet transformations”?

Definition

Given categories AA,BB,CC,DD and functors F:ABF:A\to B,G:CDG:C\to D a sheet transformation α:FG\alpha:F \Rightarrow G

A F B α C α α D C G D \array{ A & \stackrel{F}{\to} & B \\ \mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha_C}}\downarrow &\mathllap{\scriptsize{\alpha}}\Downarrow & \downarrow\mathrlap{\scriptsize{\alpha_D}} \\ C & \stackrel{G}{\to} & D }

assigns functors α C:AC\alpha_C:A\to C and α D:BD\alpha_D:B\to D called component functors such that

α DFGα C\alpha_D\circ F\Rightarrow G\circ\alpha_C

is a natural transformation.


The thing itself is indifferent to being from FF to GG, but once you declare (conceptually) that it is to be something from FF to GG, then what you have is a morphism in an arrow 22-category, as I wrote there.

Interesting! That means a morphism in a arrow 2-category is the same thing as a “sheet transformation” (or vice versa :))

Urs: it seems to me what you are getting is is the relation between 2-categories and double categories: a double category is a gadget whose 2-cells are squares not bigons. Every 2-category yields a double category by precisely the kind of operation that you are describing: take the squares of the double category to be things built from four 1-morphisms and one 2-morphism in the 2-category. Indeed, as a 2-morphism in the 2-category it is something that goes between the composites of the 1-morphisms, but the resulting square itself in the double category is indeed a 2-morphism to be regarded as going from the top horizontal to the bottom horizontal 1-morphism.

Toby: Don't you have to talk about a double bicategory to get something nontrivial to fill the squares? I may have this wrong, but that's how I remember it.

Mike Shulman: No, a double bicategory is just a double category in which both composition operations are only associative and unital up to isomorphism. Sometimes I feel like “double categories” should really have been called “double 2-categories,” since they have nontrivial 2-cells. So it is true that what Eric is interested in are just the 2-cells in the double category Sq(Cat)Sq(Cat) of “squares” or “quintets” in CatCat. As such, they have two different composition operations given by pasting.

Another way to describe it is that these are the morphisms in the 2-category 2Cat oplax(2,Cat)2Cat_{oplax}(\mathbf{2},Cat), where for 2-categories AA and BB, 2Cat oplax(A,B)2Cat_{oplax}(A,B) denotes the 2-category whose objects are 2-functors ABA\to B and whose morphisms are oplax natural transformations, and 2\mathbf{2} denotes the walking arrow. Thus an object of 2Cat oplax(2,Cat)2Cat_{oplax}(\mathbf{2},Cat) is a 2-functor 2Cat\mathbf{2}\to Cat, i.e. a functor, and a morphism is an oplax natural transformation, which is precisely what you’ve described. Composition of morphisms in 2Cat oplax(2,Cat)2Cat_{oplax}(\mathbf{2},Cat) is one of the above compositions in the double category Sq(Cat)Sq(Cat).

Last revised on October 28, 2020 at 07:19:23. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.