The term ‘topological category’ is traditional, and comes from the frequent examples in topology. It does not mean an internal category or enriched category in Top (a topologically enriched category)! (Fortunately the term topological groupoid is not taken by this tradition; indeed, the only groupoid that is a topological category over is trivial. On the other hand, there is use of the term ‘topological functor’, which we tend to avoid other than below.)
A topological category is a concrete category with nice features matching the ability to form weak and strong topologies in Top.
Most generally, the definition relates to a functor (such as the forgetful functor from to Set), but one can think of this as giving as a bundle over . Sometimes, when is in fact Set, the category satisfying the properties described belows is called a topological construct (Preuss). Usually and will be large categories.
By a space we will mean an object of , and by an algebra we will mean an object of . By a map we will mean a morphism in , and by a homomorphism we will mean a morphism in . (The reason is that, typically, will be a category of spaces with some kind of topological structure while will be, if not , then some kind of algebraic category.)
Then is a topological category over if, given any algebra and any (possibly large) family of spaces and homomorphisms (that is, a “-structured” source from ), there exists an initial lift (think: “smallest topology rendering the continuous”), which is to say
a space such that , and maps such that , and
given any space , homomorphism , and maps , if each composite equals , then there exists a unique map such that and .
Here are some illustrative commutative diagrams (if you can read them):
It follows by a clever argument that must be faithful; see Theorem 21.3 of ACC. That is also often included in the definition, in which case the uniqueness of can be left out. Thus we may think of objects of as objects of equipped with extra structure. The idea is then that is equipped with the initial structure or weak structure determined by the requirement that the homomorphisms be structure-preserving maps.
The dual concept could be called a cotopological category. However, this is not actually anything new; is topological if and only if is. This is a categorification of the theorem that any complete semilattice is a complete lattice. Thus, every topological category also has final (not usually called terminal) or strong structures, each determined by a family of homomorphisms (a -structured sink to ).
Both of these results (faithfulness and self-duality) depend on the fact that we have allowed the family to be potentially large. Counterexamples are easy to find. For instance, if is a large category with all (small) products, then the functor to the terminal category satisfies the above lifting property for small families . However, it need not satisfy the dual property (unless also has all small coproducts) nor need it be faithful.
It also follows that is a Grothendieck fibration and opfibration.
Since initial lifts have a universal property, they are unique up to unique isomorphism. However, it is traditional in some literature to ask that they be literally unique (this is done for instance in ACC). This is tantamount to deciding that should be an amnestic functor. A drawback (from an nPOV) is that this condition violates the principle of equivalence, and arguably doesn’t add anything mathematically important.
Thus, although it occurs in the literature, here we will consider it purely optional. (It is possible that some results recorded here about topological categories will depend on this assumption, but only results not respecting the principle of equivalence could be affected.)
On the other hand, the default definition above does already refer to equality of objects in the condition ; thus as stated it already violates the principle of equivalence, just as the notion of Grothendieck fibration does. But (also as for Grothendieck fibrations) this other use of equality of objects is really more of a “typing judgment”, which can be made precise by working with displayed categories instead. (In the context of homotopy type theory, the amnestic condition is equivalent to “fiberwise univalence”.)
However, if we want to, we can also formulate a “fully isomorphism-invariant” version of the definition, corresponding to the weakened bicategorical notion of Street fibration. In this case, an initial lift consists of:
a space , an isomorphism , and maps such that each composite equals and,
given any space , homomorphism , and maps , if each composite equals , then there exists a unique map such that and .
The name ‘topological category’ comes from these examples from point-set topology; these are all topological over Set:
In contrast, the category of locales is not topological over , apparently not even the category of spatial locales (equivalent to the category of sober spaces), essentially because soberification of a topological space may not preserve the underlying set.
Also, the category Diff of smooth manifolds is not topological but most categories of generalized smooth spaces are.
Outside of topology, the category of measurable spaces is topological over .
The category of topological groups is topological over Grp, the category of topological vector spaces is topological over -Vect, etc.
If is topological over , then so is any full retract of , as long as the functors involved live in .
In particular, a reflective or coreflective subcategory of is topological, as long as the reflectors or coreflectors become identity morphisms in .
The forgetful functor is not only faithful but also (because every algebra must have an initial/indiscrete topology determined by the empty source) essentially surjective (in fact surjective on the nose for the non-weak definitions). Thus it is never full (except in the trivial case where is an equivalence, of course).
If is complete or cocomplete, then so is .
If is total or cototal, then so is ; see solid functor.
If is mono-complete or epi-cocomplete, then so is .
If is well-powered or co-well-powered, then so is .
If has a factorization structure for sinks , then has one , where is the collection of morphisms in lying over -morphisms in , and the collection of final sinks in lying over -sinks in . This generalizes the lifting of orthogonal factorization systems along Grothendieck fibrations.
If is concrete, then so is . More generally, if has a generator, then is concrete over .
In particular, if is Set, then is a concrete category that is complete, cocomplete, well powered, and well copowered.
A functor between topological concrete categories , with the same base category preserves initial lifts iff it is right adjoint. It preserves final lifts iff it is left adjoint.
More generally: If a functor between topological concrete categories , with different base categories lying over a functor . If is right (left) adjoint, then is right (left) adjoint and preserves initial (final) lifts. A partial converse holds: If is right (left) adjoint to and preserves initial (final) lifts, then there is functor lying over so that is right (left) adjoint to .
If is any algebra, then there is a discrete space over induced by the empty family of maps. Similarly, we have an indiscrete space with the final structure induced by no maps. This defines functors that are respectively left and right adjoints of .
Suppose that has an initial object . Then the discrete space over is initial in . Similarly, the indiscrete space over a terminal object in is terminal in .
More generally, suppose that has products or coproducts (indexed by whichever cardinalities you may wish to consider). Then also has (co)products, lying over the (co)products in , with structures induced by the product projections or coproduct inclusions.
More general limits and colimits are constructed in a similar way. However, it is not typically the case that creates (co)limits in because creation of a limit requires that every preimage of the limiting cone is limiting. This fails for since we can coarsen the topology on the limit vertex to obtain a counterexample.
If a single algebra has been given the structure of several spaces, then there are a supremum structure and an infimum structure on induced (as the initial and final structures) by the various incarnations of its identity homomorphism. Exploiting this shows how to construct final structures out of initial ones and conversely.
If is a regular subalgebra of some , then the inclusion homomorphism makes into a subspace of , which is also a subobject in . Every regular subobject of is of this form; note however that there may be nonregular subobjects in even if all subobjects in are regular.
The theory of topological functors can be developed along the lines of Grothendieck’s theory of fibrations, where cartesian morphisms are replaced by cartesian families. In this way just as by definition “A functor is a fibration if it creates cartesian morphisms and cartesian morphism compose”, there is the definition “A functor is topological if it creates cartesian families and cartesian families compose”.
Richard Garner, Topological functors as total categories, TAC
Eduardo J. Dubuc, Luis Español, Topological functors as familiarly fibrations
arXiv (2006)
J. Martin Harvey, Topological functors from factorization, Categorical Topology: Proceedings of the International Conference, Berlin, August 27th to September 2nd, 1978. Springer Berlin Heidelberg, 1979.
Last revised on June 8, 2024 at 20:23:01. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.