additive and abelian categories
(AB1) pre-abelian category
(AB2) abelian category
(AB5) Grothendieck category
left/right exact functor
Freyd (1999) gave a sharp and clever description of the commonalities and differences between abelian categories and toposes (or, in the first place, between abelian categories and pretoposes), by introducing a finitely axiomatized theory of “AT categories”. Thus abelian categories and pretoposes are examples of AT categories; underscoring how much these structures have in common, Freyd’s theory hews so closely to both of these two basic examples that in fact every AT category splits cleanly as a product of a pretopos part and an abelian part.
Here, the properties held in common between abelian categories and pretoposes are all exactness conditions; in the AT set-up, the decisive difference between abelian categories and pretoposes is concentrated solely in the behavior of the initial object with respect to cartesian product (being in one case the cartesian monoidal unit, i.e. an element that is universally absorbed into any other, and in the other an absorbing element, i.e. an element that absorbs any other element into itself, aka a zero element or annihilating element).
There is no research we know of on AT categories. One might say that they were invented by Freyd really for the sole theoretical purpose of demonstrating the commonalities and differences between abelian categories and pretopos categories, not because AT categories are found in nature. Indeed, a “typical” AT category is something of a mythological creature with the head of an abelian lion and the body of a pretopos dragon, and serves no purpose as such, even though pure lions and pure dragons themselves serve a purpose. Some of the axioms, particular axiom “AE” below, seem expressly designed to fuse them together in ad hoc fashion.
Freyd introduces some baseline assumptions on the categories in question:
Presence of an initial object,
Presence of pushouts for pairs of arrows one of which is monic,
Presence of pushouts for kernel pairs
Each of these assumptions obviously holds in any abelian category and in any pretopos.
If we introduce predicates to express these four baseline assumptions, such as a predicate formula whose meaning is “ is a pushout pair for pairs of arrows ”, then the remaining AT axioms given below all have a simple logical structure: they can be expressed as Horn clauses in the language generated by the baseline predicates. The first 8 axioms are in fact universal Horn clauses in these predicates.
This might look like a side comment for logicians, but it might also signal that Freyd intends to invoke, if pressed for details of proofs, one of a battery of representation theorems, such as the representation theorem for regular categories whose precise formulation is in terms of Horn theories – see Categories, Allegories for examples.
Furthermore, by choosing a specific initial object, a specific pullback for each pair of arrows with common target, etc., an AT category can be cast as a model for a certain essentially algebraic theory. In other words, such “algebraic AT categories” can be internalized in any finitely complete category.
The crucial difference between “abelianness” and “toposness” is concentrated in the following definition:
Let denote the initial object, and for any object let
,
denote the two product projections.
We say is
of type T if is an isomorphism,
of type A if is an isomorphism.
With this:
A pretopos will turn out to be precisely an AT category in which every object is of type T.
An abelian category will turn out to be an AT category where every object is of type A.
Here then are the AT exactness axioms. Again, each of them is satisfied in every abelian category and in every pretopos, and according to Freyd’s thesis, any exactness condition satisfied in both classes of categories is a logical consequence of this set of axioms. Some of Freyd’s remarks in his original posting are included in parentheses.
A category meeting the baseline assumptions above is an AT category if the following 8 axioms plus axiom “AE” are satisfied.
The category is an effective regular category.
(“Yes this can be stated as universal Horn conditions on pullbacks and the special pushouts mentioned above.”)
The arrow is monic. (“Note that it follows that all maps from are monic.”)
If is mono, then any pushout square
is also a pullback, and is mono.
The functor preserves pushouts of kernel pairs, and pushouts of pairs of arrows one of which is monic.
If is epi and
In the full subcategory of type T objects (Def. ), pushouts of pairs of morphisms, one of which is monic, are universal (i.e., stable under pullback).
Define a functor by the pushout diagram
Then preserves pullbacks.
Given a morphism , if and are isomorphisms, then so is .
This is the basic list of exactness assumptions which permit a sharp comparison between pretoposes and abelian categories. From this list alone one can prove that every AT category embeds faithfully in a product of a pretopos and an abelian category. To show that every AT category is equivalent to such a product, Freyd appends the following axiom involving an existential Horn condition:
axiom (AE)
For every object , there is a map such that
is a coproduct diagram, and the canonical map is a retraction of .
To bring actual toposes into the picture, Freyd adds some more axioms, but let’s first take stock and see what this gives us so far.
For any the unique map is monic.
By axiom 2, the map is monic. The pullback-preserving functor preserves monos, so
(which is just the second projection ) is monic. The unique map is monic since it has a retraction . The result follows.
Binary coproducts exist.
Because we can take the pushout of a pair of monos , .
Coproducts are disjoint.
By axiom 3, the two coprojections , are monic, and their pullback is initial.
In this section we show that the full subcategory of type A objects forms an abelian category.
An object is of type A if and only if there exists a map to .
If is of type A, then we clearly have . Conversely, suppose there exists . Note that since is monic, there is at most one map for any object . It follows quickly that maps are in natural bijective correspondence with maps by composition with , so that is an isomorphism by the Yoneda lemma.
The full subcategory of type A objects is coreflective.
By Lemma , the subcategory of type A objects in an AT category is equivalent to the subcategory , which is the category of coalgebras for the functor . Thus the category of type A objects is comonadic.
Objects of type A are closed under binary products, finite coproducts, subobjects, and quotient objects (= cokernels of kernel pairs).
This follows from the fact that the category of type A objects is the slice category .
Before we prove the next lemma, recall that in a category with zero objects, a kernel of an arrow is an equalizer of the pair . This is the same as a pullback
Cokernels are defined dually, and can be formulated dually as certain pushouts. Since pushouts along monos exist, we can take the cokernel of any mono, and in particular the cokernel of any kernel.
In the category of type A objects, every mono is the kernel of its cokernel, and every epi is the cokernel of its kernel.
Of course, is a zero object in the category of type A objects. If is a mono in the category of type A objects, then the pushout
exists and is also a pullback, by axiom 3, and hence is the kernel of its cokernel. Now suppose is an epi in the category of type A objects. Since , we have an epi . Then, by axiom 5, the pullback
is also a pushout, so is the cokernel of its kernel.
The category of type A objects is an abelian category.
Any category with zero objects, binary products and coproducts, and in which every mono is the kernel of its cokernel and every epi is the cokernel of its kernel, is in fact an abelian category. See Freyd-Scedrov, Categories, Allegories, 1.598 (p. 95).
Now we show that the full subcategory of type T objects is a pretopos. It is clear that (since is monic), so is a type T object.
If is type A and is type T, then there exists exactly one map . Type T objects are characterized by this property.
There is exactly one morphism . Hence morphisms are in bijection with maps , of which there is exactly one. For the second statement, suppose that has the property that there is exactly one map for each type A object. Such objects are closed under products, and is such an object; therefore is such an object. On the other hand, is of type A since it projects to . Hence there is at most one morphism , and it follows that is the identity, so that . Thus is of type T.
The initial object is strict in the category of type T objects.
Given of type T and , we know is type A, and therefore by Lemma there is exactly one map . Hence is the identity, and of course so is . So is initial.
The full subcategory of objects of type T is closed under products, coproducts, subobjects, and quotient objects.
Closure under products and subobjects is immediate from Lemma . Closure under quotients and coproducts follows from axiom 4.
The full subcategory of objects of type T is a pretopos.
Corollary gives finite completeness, coproducts, and quotients of kernel pairs. Axiom 6 gives that in the full subcategory of objects, pushouts along monos are stable under pullback, and the initial object is stable under pullback in the category of T objects, because it is strict by Corollary . It follows that coproducts are universal in the category of T objects. They are also disjoint by an earlier result, so the category of T objects is extensive. It is also effective regular by axiom 1, hence a pretopos.
In this section we show that every AT category is the product of the abelian category of type A objects and the pretopos of type T objects.
Let us first observe that the coreflector (see Proposition )
is left exact (as all coreflectors are), and
Preserves the initial object (by axiom 2),
Preserves pushouts of kernel pairs, and pushouts of pairs of arrows one of which is monic (axiom 4),
And therefore also preserves coproducts.
A functor between AT categories which is left exact and which preserves such classes of finite colimits may be called a morphism of AT categories. Hence the coreflector is a morphism of AT categories.
Next let us observe that the subcategory is reflective; the reflector is the functor defined above by means of a suitable pushout. The reflector clearly preserves any colimits that exist, and preserves pullbacks (by axiom 7), so
is also a morphism of AT categories. Therefore we have a morphism of AT categories
and now we wish to prove, under a suitable additional axiom (also satisfied by every abelian category and every pretopos), that this is an equivalence.
The functor is faithful.
The functor is left exact and therefore preserves kernels. By axiom 8, reflects isomorphisms. It follows immediately from these two facts that is faithful.
With this result, Freyd’s “first task” is complete: any AT category may be faithfully represented in a product of a pretopos and an abelian category.
At this point we bring in axiom AE, def. , for its debut appearance. It may be helpful to consider that is by definition the cokernel appearing in the exact sequence
and that axiom AE asserts that this exact sequence splits (with splitting ), in such a way that is the coproduct of the end terms.
The functor is full.
Suppose given maps , , and contemplate the diagram
Since , the two obvious arrows , combine to give an arrow . It is straightforward to check that (because the functor kills the type T summands) and that .
The functor is an equivalence.
All that is left to check is that is essentially surjective, but this is clear because given a type A object and a type T object , we have (use axiom 4 plus the fact that ), and
which completes the proof.
This completes Freyd’s “second task”.
In order to beef up the type T objects to a topos, Freyd imposes some extra structure on top of the AT axioms. Since it is now the topos axioms that are in the ascendant, I will christen these categories TA categories.
Thus, a TA category is an AT category together with
Functions ,
Functions , of the form , ,
An operation which assigns to each pair of morphisms , (where and are assumed to be type T), a morphism .
This data is to satisfy the following axioms:
is monic and , are of type T,
The composite of relations
is equal to
If
is a pullback and is of type T, then .
Freyd: “Note that in the full category of type-T objects, yields power-objects with , , naming the universal relations. (The third axiom provides the uniqueness condition.)”
And: “In any abelian category the only type T object is the zero object, which forces for abelian categories.”
And finally: “It’s routine that both and preserve the new structure. We can now remove the existential from AE. Define as the image of . The third task is finished with:
This section is likely to be rewritten and cleaned up.
Last revised on July 11, 2023 at 09:14:15. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.