The concept of a closed subtopos generalizes the concept of a closed subspace from topology to toposes.
Let be a subterminal object of a topos . Then defines a Lawvere-Tierney topology on , whose corresponding subtopos is called the closed subtopos associated to .
The reflector into the sheaves can be constructed explicitly as the join with , i.e. is the pushout of and under .
A topology that is of this form for some subterminal object is called closed.
In case is the topos of sheaves on a topological space , a subterminal object is just an open subset of and the closed subtopos corresponding to it is equivalent to .
The subterminal object in is associated with an open subtopos as well e.g. in the case of on a space this yields .
Moreover, given a Lawvere-Tierney topology on a topos with corresponding subtopos , we a get a canonical subterminal object associated to by taking the -closure of . The corresponding closed and open subtoposes associated to provide a ‘closure’ , called l’adhérence in (SGA4, p.461), respectively, an ‘exterior’ for .
Let a subterminal object and and the corresponding closed, resp. open subtoposes. Then and are complements for each other in the lattice of subtoposes.
For the proof see (Johnstone (2002), pp.212,215).
Closed subtoposes that are Boolean are parametrized by automorphisms of the subobject classifier as the next proposition documents:
Let be a topos. Then automorphisms of correspond bijectively to closed Boolean subtoposes. The group operation on corresponds to symmetric difference of subtoposes.
This result appears in Johnstone (1979).
The following result is a part of the so called (dense,closed)-factorization.
Let be dominant and a closed inclusion at the same time. Then is an isomorphism.
Proof: Recall that are in the closed subtopos precisely when they satisfy with the subterminal object associated to . But is dominant, or what comes to the same for inclusions: dense, hence is in and therefore . From this follows , which in turn implies that all are in .
This says that the only closed subtopos of a topos that is dense, is itself.
It follows e.g. that Boolean toposes have no non-trivial dense subtoposes since all their subtoposes are closed (and open, as well). Of course, this follows also from the fact that a Boolean topos coincides with its double negation subtopos and the latter is the smallest dense subtopos!
M. Artin, A. Grothendieck, J. L. Verdier, Théorie des Topos et Cohomologie Etale des Schémas (SGA4), LNM 269 Springer Heidelberg 1972. (Exposé IV 9.3.4-9.4., pp.456ff)
Peter Johnstone, Topos Theory , Academic Press New York 1977. (Dover reprint 2014, pp.93-95)
Peter Johnstone, Automorphisms of , Algebra Universalis 9 (1979) pp.1-7.
Peter Johnstone, Sketches of an Elephant vol. I, Oxford UP 2002. (A4.5., pp.204-220)
Last revised on May 11, 2016 at 12:44:47. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.