transfinite arithmetic, cardinal arithmetic, ordinal arithmetic
prime field, p-adic integer, p-adic rational number, p-adic complex number
arithmetic geometry, function field analogy
Surreal numbers (or Conway numbers, after John H. Conway) are a kind of numbers that originally arose in the context of combinatorial games?, as a kind of generalized quantity for measuring strength of positions. The class of surreal numbers forms an ordered field in which any small ordered field may be embedded, so that the field of surreal numbers forms a universal field for expressing any set-bounded degree of infinite and infinitesimal quantities. Any ordinal number may be construed as a surreal number, and new surreal numbers may be defined from old ones by generalizing the notion of Dedekind cut. Surreal numbers are a very large extension of real numbers, where one may make sense of fanciful quantities such as
The term “surreal number” was introduced by Donald Knuth, who wrote a short novel about a couple who check out from Western civilization and live on a remote beach in India and who, finding a mysterious engraved stone and with an abundance of time to spend on things besides food and sex, discover for themselves surreal numbers and their delightful properties.
The notions of Conway game and Conway number, as given by Conway in his book On Numbers and Games, are disarmingly simple-looking. Here is a Conway-style definition of game:
The second sentence is a shorthand way of saying this is supposed to be a recursive or inductive definition: if a collection of left options and a collection is given, one can construct a game . Games are built recursively, starting with .
Here is a Conway-style definition of number:
followed immediately by a recursive definition of :
Ultimately, each number is considered to be a (Dedekind) cut between the set of left options (which are ‘below’ ) and the set of right options (which are ‘above’ ).
Equality of numbers is a derived notion:
Finally, field operations on surreal numbers are defined recursively:
is defined by letting be the set , and the set ;
is defined by letting be the set of negatives of elements of , and the set of negatives of ;
is defined by letting be the set
and be the set
The style of such definitions is familiar from material set theory, where elements are conceived to be sets of elements, which themselves have elements, and so on, down to a bedrock established by a foundation axiom. In fact, games can be axiomatized as elements of a structure with two predicates , satisfying some set-theoretic axioms.
The definition of multiplication is the most involved. We can summarize it by saying that the left set gets contributions from like sets, and the right set gets contributions from opposite kinds. For example, is , so the left-hand contributions to the left set are
The other contributions work out similarly: everything ends up being the empty set, so the answer is .
Conway motivates this definition from the observation that, if and , then and . And so, if multiplication makes any sense at all, we should have and thus . Therefore, elements of this form should appear in . Following this kind of logic for the other possible combinations leads to the definition of multiplication given above.
The definition of for numbers as formulated by Conway leans heavily upon properties of negation, and in particular the classical principle of excluded middle. However, it can be made more constructive by defining separately from :
This approach works up to a point. However, it encounters a problem in proving that multiplication is well-defined, i.e. that it respects equality. We can prove that if then and hence , and that if then and hence ; but without excluded middle we can’t say that every is either or , so how can we conclude that ? It is unknown whether there is a solution to this problem.
It is a routine matter to rewrite the definitions in a more structural fashion, say within ETCS. In outline, a game is a rooted tree with no infinite branches and equipped with a labeling of each edge by a symbol or . The nodes are called positions of the game. The root is the initial position, and starting from any position, there are positions that a player named may move to, and positions that the other player may move to, according to the edge-labelings. Any sequence of moves proceeding from the initial position (and not necessarily alternating between and ) must eventually terminate, since there are no infinite branches.
Each position has a definite depth , where is the number of edges one must back-track through along the unique path that leads back to the initial position. A tree is thus an internal presheaf on the ordered set , whose value at the initial object is terminal (occupied by the initial position), and where is the set of positions at depth . A move is a morphism in the corresponding category of elements of the presheaf, and moves are labeled by or .
In this set-up, the condition of no infinite branches plays the role of a foundation axiom, and inductive arguments tend to devolve upon the use of the principle of dependent choice.
Numbers may be similarly elaborated within this context. The definition of on numbers is ultimately derived from a posetal reflection of a category of games (with strategies as morphisms), and the definition of addition of numbers is derived from a Day convolution product on the category of games. More information may be found at Conway game?.
In homotopy type theory, the surreal numbers can be defined as a higher inductive type, roughly following Conway’s definition but imposing the “defined” notion of equality as the “actual” equality with an identification-constructor. This can also be done constructively by separating from , as remarked above. See chapter 11.6 of the HoTT Book.
An axiomatic approach to surreal numbers analogous to the approach to sets and ordinals in algebraic set theory can be found in Rangel-Mariano 19.
The surreal numbers form a large (i.e., proper-class size) real closed field with exponentiation.
To some degree, and with appropriate caveats, one can do analysis and number theory on surreal numbers. We refer to Conway’s book for more information.
John H. Conway, On Numbers and Games ( edition), A.K. Peters, Ltd (2001).
Donald E. Knuth, Surreal numbers, Addison-Wesley (1974)
The HoTT Book, chapter 11.6.
Dimi Rocha Rangel, Hugo Luiz Mariano, An algebraic (set) theory of surreal numbers, I, 2019, arxiv
Last revised on August 11, 2021 at 05:00:59. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.