nLab
coordination

Context

Philosophy

Physics

physics, mathematical physics, philosophy of physics

Surveys, textbooks and lecture notes


theory (physics), model (physics)

experiment, measurement, computable physics

Contents

page under construction

General Idea

Coordination concerns the relationship between scientific theory and empirical data. A physical theory, written say as a set of equations or similar data, does not by itself allow the formation of predictions. In addition we need some way of mediating between this theory and what our instruments can detect about the universe.

For example, to connect Einstein's equations about the curvature of space-time to predicted observations of the direction of light coming from distant stars and passing close to the sun, general relativity postulates that light follows a null geodesic.

History

The term coordination is a translation of the German Zuordnung. The latter has a long history of use with mathematics as something like function. Its use in philosophy stretches back to Hermann von Helmholtz?’s Zeichentheorie, and was taken up later by a number of philosophers, especially by those, such as Ernst Cassirer, trying to understand the implications for epistemology of the profound transformations which took place in mathematics and physics at the turn of the nineteenth century (special relativity, general relativity, quantum mechanics).

In his Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre (1918), Moritz Schlick (Schlick18 relies heavily on the notion of coordination, proposing that it should be understood as a simple set-theoretic mapping between the system of implicitly defined terms of a physical theory and some system of given objects or elements of sensation. A few years later, Hans Reichenbach, by contrast, argued that the act of coordination was no mere mapping between existing systems, but itself played a constitutive role in defining the objects of knowledge themselves.

The difficulty concerning coordinative definitions is similar to that concerning elementary facts: the physical thing that is coordinated is not an immediate perceptual experience but must be constructed from such experience by means of an interpretation. If I establish the coordinative definition “a light ray is a straight line”, then the coordinated physical thing, the light ray, is a construction going beyond perception. (1924, p. 8)

A central issue between these accounts is that the more you press on the constitutive function of coordinating principles, the more it seems that the entities referred to by physics owe their characteristics to our conceptual framing rather than to how things are in themselves.

In quantum mechanics

Bohrification

The idea of Bohr toposes might be regarded as an attempt to formalize coordination for observables in quantum mechanics. There the idea is roughly that to a quantum mechanical system one assigns a topos (the “Bohr topos”) such that the (or some of the) propositions in the internal logic of this topos match propositions about observables of the physical system.

Relation to interpretation of QM

Coordination is different from – in fact somewhat orthogonal to – interpretation of quantum mechanics. For instance a coordination in quantum mechanics involves relating self-adjoint operators to certain experiments. Given this coordination, the theory assigns expectation values for the outcomes of the experiment, but it does not necessarily offer an “interpretation why” these propbabilities are predicted.

On the other hand, it might be that a good formulation of the coordination process makes the need/desire for interpretations diminish. This was argued by (Tanona 10)

…the characterization of collapse as a separate physical process is misguided because the phenomenon which collapse is supposed to address concerns not an actual process within quantum mechanical theory but rather the coordination between empirical measurements and representations of quantum systems. Until we first get clear on this relationship, it is premature to propose new processes to account for features of that relationship.

References

  • Hans Reichenbach (1969). Axiomatization of the Theory of Relativity. Berkeley: University of California Press. Original German edition published in 1924.

  • Thomas Ryckman (1991), Conditio sine qua non? Zuordnung in the Early Epistemologies of Cassirer and Schlick, Synthese 88(1), pp. 57-95.

  • Moritz Schlick (1918), Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre.

  • Scott Tanona, Theory, coordination, and empirical meaning in modern physics, in Mary Domski and Michael Dickson (eds.), Discourse on a New Method: Reinvigorating the Marriage of History and Philosophy of Science. Open Court (2010), pp. 423-454.

Revised on March 1, 2014 15:26:09 by Urs Schreiber (89.204.135.112)