By (or ) is denoted the category of toposes. Usually this means:
objects are sheaf toposes;
morphisms are geometric morphisms of toposes.
(In parts of the literature this is denoted merely “”, but that clashes with the common notation for the the category of topological spaces.)
This is naturally a 2-category, where
That is, a 2-morphism is a natural transformation (which is, by mate calculus, equivalent to a natural transformation between direct images).
Thus, is equivalent to both of
the (non-full) sub-2-category of the 1-opposite of Cat on categories that are sheaf toposes and morphisms that are the inverse image parts of geometric morphisms, and
the (non-full) sub-2-category of the 2-opposite of Cat on categories that are sheaf toposes and morphisms that are the direct image parts of geometric morphisms.
(elementary toposes and logical functors) We obtain a very different 2-category of toposes if we take objects to be elementary toposes and morphisms the logical functors; this 2-category is sometimes denoted or .
The operation of forming categories of sheaves
embeds topological spaces into toposes. For a continuous map we have that is the geometric morphism
with the direct image and the inverse image.
Strictly speaking, this functor is not an embedding if we consider as a 1-category and as a 2-category, since it is then not fully faithful in the 2-categorical sense—there can be nontrivial 2-cells between geometric morphisms between toposes of sheaves on topological spaces.
However, if we regard as a (1,2)-category where the 2-cells are inequalities in the specialization ordering, then this functor does become a 2-categorically full embedding (i.e. an equivalence on hom-categories) if we restrict to the full subcategory of sober spaces. This embedding can also be extended from to the entire category of locales (which can be viewed as “Grothendieck 0-toposes”).
There are similar full embeddings and of sheaf (1-)toposes into 2-sheaf 2-toposes and sheaf (n,1)-toposes for .
Note that these embeddings are not the identity functor on underlying categories: a 1-topos is not itself an -topos, instead we have to take -sheaves on a suitable generating site for it.
There is a canonical forgetful functor LocPrCat assigning underlying locally presentable categories.
This 2-functor has a right 2-adjoint (Bunge & Carboni 1995 p 235).
The 2-category is not all that well-endowed with limits, but its slice categories are finitely complete as 2-categories, and is closed under finite limits in . In particular, the terminal object in is the topos Set .
The supply with colimits is better:
All small (indexed) 2-colimits in exists and are computed as (indexed) 2-limits in Cat of the underlying inverse image functors.
This appears as Moerdijk, theorem 2.5
Let
be a 2-pullback in such that
are both pseudomonic morphisms
is an effective epimorphism;
then the diagram of inverse image functors
is a 2-pullback in Cat and so by the above the original square is also a 2-pushout.
This appears as theorem 5.1 in (BungeLack)
The 2-category is an extensive category. Same for toposes bounded over a base.
This is in (BungeLack, proposition 4.3).
The Cartesian product of presheaf toposes in is the presheaf topos on the product category of their sites:
More generally, for a Grothendieck topology on , the product in of the sheaf topos is the sheaf topos over the product site , where is the Grothendieck topology on the product category generated from products of covering sieves from and :
(cf. Pitts 1985 proof of Thm. 2.3, Valero 2018 p 98-99)
Since every sheaf topos admits a site that has all finite limits, we first consider the topos-product of presheaf toposes (1) under the assumption that the sites have all finite limits. (We refer to these small categories as “sites” already, even though in the presheaf case they are as such equipped with the trivial Grothendieck topology).
To check the defining universal property of a Cartesian product, we use that geometric morphisms
between sheaf toposes (generally between locally presentable categories) correspond bijectively to finite limit-preserving cocontinuous functors
(by the adjoint functor theorem for locally presentable categories).
Then writing
for the canonical projection functors out of the product category of the given sites, and writing
for the corresponding pre-composition functors on presheaves (which presverve all (co)limits since (co)limits of presheaves are computed objectwise), it is sufficient to show that for and
a pair of cocontinuous and finitely continuous functors, there is a unique such functor
which makes the following diagram commute:
To this end, observe that for a representable presheaf
(with the Yoneda embedding on the right)
we evidently have
(where “” denotes the terminal object of ). It follows that to be finite-limit preserving, and hence in particular finite product-preserving, the dashed map must send representables
to
where we have used, in order of appearance, that:
limits in a product category are computed via the limits in the factor categories,
is assumed to preserve finite limits,
the equivalences (3) hold,
the above triangles commute.
So this fixes the values of on all representables. But thereby it actually fixes its values on all of , since the latter is the free cocompletion of (all presheaves are colimits of representables) and since is also required to be cocontinuous and hence must preserve these colimits.
This establishes the claim
for the case that the have all finite limits. To conclude, it is now sufficient to observe that this construction descends to sheaf toposes as claimed.
To that end, just to note that for a geometric morphism between presheaf toposes to descend to sheaves is equivalent to sending covering morphisms to local isomorphisms (cf. at morphism of sites, because, by adjunction, this is equivalently the condition for to take sheaves to sheaves, whence as such its left adjoint is followed by sheafification).
A category of simplicial sheaves is the Topos-product of the corresponding sheaf topos of Set-values sheaves with the topos of simplicial sets, the latter being the presheaf topos over the simplex category:
Let
be a diagram of toposes. Then its pullback in the (2,1)-category version of is computed, roughly, by the pushout of their sites of definition.
More in detail: there exist sites , , and with finite limits and morphisms of sites
such that
Let then
be the pushout of the underlying categories in the non-full subcategory of categories with finite limits and limit-preserving functors between them (cf. Lurie, prop. 6.3.4.3).
Let moreover
be the reflective subcategory obtained by localization at the class of morphisms generated by the inverse image of the coverings of and the inverse image of the coverings of .
Then
is a pullback square.
This appears as Lurie, prop. 6.3.4.6.
For localic toposes this reduces to the statement of localic reflection: the pullback of toposes is given by the of pullback the underlying locales which in turn is the pushout of the corresponding frames.
The free loop space object of a topos in Topos is called the isotropy group of a topos.
Topos
On Cartesian products and base change in :
On the characterization of colimits in :
The fact that is extensive:
General limits and colimits of toposes:
(discussed for (∞,1)-toposes, but the statements are verbatim true in the (2,1)-category category )
The adjunction between toposes and locally presentable categories:
See also:
Last revised on June 11, 2025 at 07:00:00. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.