Riemann integration, Lebesgue integration
line integral/contour integration
integration of differential forms
integration over supermanifolds, Berezin integral, fermionic path integral
Kontsevich integral, Selberg integral, elliptic Selberg integral
integration in ordinary differential cohomology
integration in differential K-theory
In measure theory, measure spaces are used in the general theory of measure and integration, somewhat analogous to the role played by topological spaces in the study of continuity.
For the general theory of measure spaces, we first need a measurable space , that is a set equipped with a collection of measurable sets complete under certain operations. Then this becomes a measure space by throwing in a function from to a space of values (such as the real line) that gets along with the set-theoretic operations that has. If is a measurable set, then is called the measure of with respect to .
The original notation for an integral (going back to Gottfried Leibniz) was
(where would be replaced by some formula in the variable ). In modern measure theory, we can now understand this as the integral of the measurable function on the interval relative to Lebesgue measure. If we wish to generalise from Lebesgue measure to an arbitrary measure and generalise from to an arbitrary measurable set , then we can write
instead. Now, if is not given by a formula but rather explicitly named, then there is no need for the dummy variable , so we should write
However, it has been more common to keep the symbol ‘’ and write
(Note that ‘’ can be read as ‘with respect to’ in both (1) and (4), although meaning different things; in the former case, it indicates the dummy variable, while in the latter case, it indicates the measure.) This notation then leads to replacing (2) with
This last notation, however, hides the fact that integrating a function with respect to a measure is a way of multiplying a function by a measure to get a new measure; the integral of on with respect to is simply the measure of with respect to , as can be seen in (3). Compare also notation for Radon-Nikodym derivatives.
It is also possible to take the entire expression ‘’ as the name of the measure, writing even where the common notation is . In that case, the common expression (4) is literally the same as (what would otherwise be) (3), although (5) is not quite the same as (what would otherwise be) (2).
We will use (3) below (although other forms may well be found on other pages).
See Usenet discussion, and contrast (5) with the Stieltjes integral. (The point is that it is , not just , that gives us the relevant measure in (1).) The notation (3) has also been used in an introductory graduate-level course by John Baez.
There is also some variation in notation as to whether to use a roman ‘’ or an italic ‘’; roman is more common in England and italic in America. But of course, that variation should not cause any difficulties!
A measure space is a measurable space equipped with a measure. There are many different kinds of measures; we start with the most specific and then consider generalisations. The motivating example is Lebesgue measure on the unit interval.
Let be a measurable space. A probability measure on (due to Andrey Kolmogorov) is a function from the collection of measurable sets to the unit interval such that:
(Part of the latter condition is the requirement that the sum on the right-hand side must converge.)
It is sometimes stated (but in fact follows from the above) that:
The first of these conditions will follow for all of the generalised notions of measure below, but the second usually will not. Related query discussion is archived here.
From now on, we drop the condition ; the next step is to generalize the target of , as follows:
We define an infinite measure by replacing the domain of by an ideal of such that the following saturation condition is satisfied: if is a disjoint family of elements of and exists (and is finite), then . The countable additivity condition should now be modified to require .
An infinite measure is semifinite if for any there is such that and . The Radon-Nikodym theorem shows that semifinite complex-valued measures that are absolutely continuous with respect to some fixed localizable measure form a free module over the algebra of complex-valued measurable functions (not necessarily bounded).
Some further terms:
Remarks:
Another possibility is to generalize the source of ; instead of using a -algebra on , we could use a -ring or even a -ring. These versions are mostly more about changing the definition of measurable space, so refer there for details of the definitions; however, we note that (3), when is a -ring, should state that the left-hand side exists (that is, the union is measurable) if the right-hand side converges. Generalizing in this way is complementary to generalizing the target above; in particular it may allow one to avoid dealing with . For example, while Lebesgue measure is only a positive measure on a -algebra, it is a finite positive measure on the -ring of bounded measurable sets. Indeed, every signed measure gives rise to finite measure on its -ring of finitely measurable sets (as defined below); conversely, every -finite measure can be recovered from this by imposing (3) in all cases.
Yet another possibility is to drop countable additivity, replacing it with finite additivity. The result is a finitely additive measure, sometimes called a charge to avoid the red herring principle; in contrast, the usual sort of measure may be called countably additive. For a charge, one could replace with an algebra (or even a ring) of sets; again see measurable space for these definitions.
Finally, an extended measure takes values in the set of extended real numbers. Here we have the problem that, even when considering finite additivity, we might have to add and . While we might simply require that this never happens (so that at least one of and must be finite if they have opposite signs and ), this does not include some examples that we want (and in fact it would follow that and cannot both be values of after all). To deal with this, we define an extended measure to be a formal difference of positive measures; whenever this is not of the form and is otherwise undefined. Note that the set of extended measures on is a quotient set of the set of pairs of positive measures; we say that if whenever either side is defined, that is if and are the same as partial functions from to .
Any extended measure restricts to an infinite signed measure, taking to be the set of elements of with a finite measure. Vice versa, an infinite signed measure canonically extends to an extended measure: we can define and as usual and then take the formal difference .
Just like how in point-free topology, one takes the opens to be fundamental and defines a locale as a frame of opens, in point-free measure theory, one takes the measurables to be fundamental and defines a measurable space as a -complete Boolean algebra of measurables.
Then the various notions of measures and measure spaces above also make sense on the -complete Boolean algebra, but where the countable union and intersection of measurable subsets in a traditional measurable space is replaced with the countable join and meet of measurables in the -complete Boolean algebra. For example, a probability measure on a -complete Boolean algebra is a function such that
The measure of the top element is one:
Countable additivity: whenever for all natural numbers and where .
In Henry Cheng's constructive theory of measure, the definition of measurable space becomes more complicated; the main point is that a single measurable set is replaced by a complemented pair . Once that is understood, very little needs to be changed to define a measure space.
In the requirements (1–3), the constants and and the operation are interpreted by formal de Morgan duality, as explained at Cheng measurable space. The convergence requirement in (3) should be interpreted in the strong sense of located convergence and is no longer trivial for positive measures. We must add a further requirement to enforce the idea that is the measure of alone, as follows:
In general, a measurable set is any set such that is a complemented pair for some set ; the term ‘measurable set’ in the classical theory should be interpreted as either ‘mesurable set’ or ‘complemented pair’ in the constructive theory, depending on context. Usually both interpretations will actually work, but often only the first set of the pair will matter, thanks to the axiom above.
We will mention other occasional fine points in the constructive theory when they occur; the main outline does not change.
I need to check Bishop & Bridges to see if there are any other changes, but I don't think so; that is, I went through the following, and it all seems correct as it is. —Toby
In measure theory, a measure on a -frame or more generally a -complete distributive lattice is a valuation such that the elements are mutually disjoint and the probability valuation is denumerably/countably additive
Given a measure space , a -null -measurable set is a measurable set such that whenever is measurable; a -null set is any subset of a null measurable set. In a positive measure space, we don't have to bother with ; will be a null measurable set as long as .
A -full -measurable set is a measurable set such that for every measurable set ; a -full set is any superset of a full measurable set. In a probability measure space, we don't have to bother with ; will be a full measurable set as long as . Classically, a full set is precisely the complement of a null set, but this doesn't hold in the constructive theory.
A property of elements of holds -almost everywhere if the set of values where it holds is full.
A measure is complete if every full set is measurable. We may form the completion of a measure space by accepting as a measurable set the intersection of any set and a full set; these -measurable sets will automatically form a -algebra (or whatever originally was). Classically, a measure is complete if and only if every null set is measurable and a set is -measurable if and only if it is the symmetric difference between a measurable set and a null set.
A finitely -measurable set is a measurable set such that is finite whenever is measurable; a -finitely -measurable set is any union of countably many finitely measurable sets. Again, we don't have to bother with in a positive measure space. Note that a measure space is ()-finite if and only if every measurable set is ()-finitely measurable. The finitely measurable sets form a -ring, and the -finitely measurable sets form a -ring.
Recall that a -measurable function from to some other measurable space is any function such that the preimage under of a measurable set is always measurable (or something more complicated in the constructive theory). Now that we have a measure space, let a -measurable function be a partial function from to some other measurable space such that the domain of is full and the preimage under of a measurable set is always -measurable (that is measurable in the completion of ), and let two such functions be -equivalent if their equaliser is a full set. We are really interested in the quotient set under this equivalence and so identify equivalent -measurable functions. Classically, every -measurable function is equivalent to some (total) -measurable function, so the definition is simpler in that case; however, partial functions still come up naturally in the classical theory, so it can be convenient to allow them rather than (as is usually done in a rigorous treatment) systematically replacing them with total functions.
A -integrable function is a -measurable function such that the integral (as defined below) exists for every measurable set ; it is enough to check . Equivalently, we may say that it is a -measurable function such that the extended measure (also defined below) is actually a finite measure. (In any case, we get a finite measure if is integrable.)
In the following, ‘measurable’ will mean -measurable. That is, we assume that is complete and identify -equivalent functions. We will also assume that is a positive measure until I make sure of what must be done to generalise.
Given a measure , a measurable set , and a measurable function , we will define the integral
(see above for variations in notation) in stages, from the simplest form of to the most arbitrary.
Each measurable subset induces a measurable characteristic function where if , if . (In the constructive theory, where is a complemented pair, is a partial function with a full domain, so is still a measurable function as defined above.) In general, we have
so from now on we will assume that we are integrating over all of (and drop the subscript).
A positive simple function is a finite -linear combination of measurable characteristic functions; the first form of integral that we define is
The integral is extended to all measurable functions by the rule
if this supremum converges. Classically, the integral either converges or diverges to infinity, so exists in some sense in any case; the possibilities are more complicated constructively.
For any measurable function , define and by
so that , . Then the final definition is
if both integrals on the right converge. Classically, the other possibilities are , , and ; not much can be done with the latter.
A measurable function is integrable with respect to if this integral converges. It can be proved that all of the definitions above are consistent; that is, if the final definition is applied to a simple function, then it agrees with the original definition.
If takes values in the field of complex numbers or in some more general Banach space , then we can still ask whether is integrable. If it is, then we say that is absolutely integrable. We can then define the integral of ; we always have
This integral is easy to define if has a basis; for example, a measurable complex-valued function is integrable iff both its real and imaginary parts are integrable, and we have
I need to check HAF for more details here in the general case. In particular, something can be integrable without being absolutely integrable (although not if it's complex-valued, of course) or indeed even without being valued in a (pseudo)normed space.
The vector space of -valued integrable functions is itself a Banach space, using the norm
Note that we must use the notion of measurable function as an equivalence class of functions to get a Banach space here; otherwise we have only a pre-Banach space (that is, a complete pseudonormed vector space).
This Banach space is called a Lebesgue space and is denoted , , or just , depending on context. The default value of is usually either or , depending on the author. More general Lebesgue spaces of the form also exist; is in precisely when is integrable, and we use
as the norm. (At least, this is so for ; see Lebesgue space for generalizations to other values of .)
Note that
makes into a -valued measure whenever is an integrable -valued function. When is -valued and is a signed measure, then is an extended measure which is finite iff is integrable. We have
Thus integration can be seen as a way of multiplying a function by a measure to get another measure.
The Radon-Nikodym derivative is about reversing this (dividing two measures to get a function).
Other topics: absolute continuity, etc. (Refer to <http://tobybartels.name/notes/#Radon>.)
Every commutative von Neumann algebra is isomorphic to the Lebesgue space where is some measure (which is irrelevant) on a localisable measurable space, and this extends to a duality between localisable measurable spaces and commutative von Neumann algebras. This is similar to the correspondence between commutative -algebras and locally compact Hausdorff spaces, which is the central approach to noncommutative geometry. It is useful to exploit the intuition that the theory of (noncommutative) von Neumann algebras is a noncommutative analogue of classical measure theory.
The pointless version of the notion of measurable space is the notion of measurable locale.
In the context of fiber integration in generalized cohomology, the analog of a measure is an orientation in generalized cohomology.
The density of a subset can be considered as taking the measure of sets normally considered to be not well behaved in measure theory, such as infinite subsets of the natural numbers.
See the references at measure theory.
For measures on -frames, see
Discussion via Boolean toposes is in
Matthew Jackson, A sheaf-theoretic approach to measure theory, 2006. (pdf)
Simon Henry, Measure theory over boolean toposes, Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambirdge Philosophical Society, 2016 (arXiv:1411.1605)
Last revised on October 19, 2024 at 02:34:06. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.