basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
The ordinal numbers admit two inequalities: a strict one and a non-strict one . When the ordinals are defined in material set theory in the von Neumann style as “the set of all smaller ordinals”, these relations are identified with (set membership?) and (containment). And when ordinals are defined in a structural theory as certain well-ordered sets, the relation refers to inclusion as an initial subset? (a simulation) while refers to such an inclusion as the strict slice of some element of .
In classical mathematics, and are definable in terms of each other’s negation: if and only if , and similarly if and only if . However, in constructive mathematics this is no longer true (although can still be defined from in a more round-about way). This phenomenon occurs for other ordered structures as well; for instance, for the real numbers. (For the most commonly used notions of real number, is definable as the negation of , but not conversely.) In general, there are certain laws we may expect such a pair of inequalities to satisfy, such as:
For the constructive ordinal numbers, these are all satisfied except for the last one. In fact, it’s easy to see that if implies for all , then excluded middle holds: consider and and for some proposition .
However, Paul Taylor (Taylor) realized that this last property can be recovered by essentially “restricting to the subclass of ordinals for which it holds hereditarily”. These are the plump ordinals.
An ordinal is plump if
It is not obvious that this definition is sound (i.e. non-circular), but it can be shown to be so based on a well-founded relation (other than itself). It does, however, require the existence of power sets, so it is not obviously sensible in predicative mathematics which denies the existence of those.
is trivially plump.
Since is plump, is also plump.
More generally, any subset of (which may be thought of as a truth value) is a plump ordinal.
But (the set of classical truth values) with is plump if and only if excluded middle holds.
In contrast, (the set of all truth values) with (as the only instance of ) is plump. So is the plump version of , equal to iff excluded middle holds.
The plump version of may be quite large; it consists of all lower sets (downwards-closed collections) of truth values. So it includes , , and , the other truth values between and , the downset (the lower set generated by ) of any given truth value (not just and ), the lower set generated by two not-necessarily-comparable truth values and , etc. But if excluded middle holds, then it's just .
Generalizing most of these examples, if is a plump ordinal, then the successor , consisting of all lower sets of , is also a plump ordinal. This is bigger than , in that if and , then excluded middle holds.
Any downwards-closed subset of a plump ordinal is also a plump ordinal.
Paul Taylor, Intuitionistic sets and ordinals, Journal of Symbolic Logic, 61:705-744, 1996, available here
See also Section 6.7 of Paul Taylor, Practical Foundations of Mathematics, here.
Last revised on September 23, 2023 at 03:18:47. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.