natural deduction metalanguage, practical foundations
type theory (dependent, intensional, observational type theory, homotopy type theory)
computational trinitarianism =
propositions as types +programs as proofs +relation type theory/category theory
equality (definitional, propositional, computational, judgemental, extensional, intensional, decidable)
identity type, equivalence of types, definitional isomorphism
isomorphism, weak equivalence, homotopy equivalence, weak homotopy equivalence, equivalence in an (∞,1)-category
Examples.
(in category theory/type theory/computer science)
of all homotopy types
of (-1)-truncated types/h-propositions
homotopy theory, (∞,1)-category theory, homotopy type theory
flavors: stable, equivariant, rational, p-adic, proper, geometric, cohesive, directed…
models: topological, simplicial, localic, …
see also algebraic topology
Introductions
Definitions
Paths and cylinders
Homotopy groups
Basic facts
Theorems
In intensional type theory, identity types behave like path space objects; this viewpoint is called homotopy type theory. This induces furthermore a notion of homotopy fibers, hence of homotopy equivalences between types.
On the other hand, if type theory contains a universe Type, so that types can be considered as points of , then between two types we also have an identity type . The univalence axiom says that these two notions of “sameness” for types are the same.
Extensionality principles like function extensionality, propositional extensionality (where and are h-propositions, and univalence (“typal extensionality”) are naturally regarded as a stronger form of identity of indiscernibles. In particular, the consistency of univalence means that in Martin-Löf type theory without univalence, one cannot define any predicate that provably distinguishes isomorphic types; thus isomorphic types are “externally indiscernible”, and univalence incarnates that principle internally by making them identical.
The name univalence (due to Voevodsky) comes from the following reasoning. A fibration or bundle of some sort is commonly said to be universal if every other bundle of the same sort is a pullback of in a unique way (up to homotopy). Less commonly, a bundle is said to be versal if every other bundle is a pullback of it in some way, not necessarily unique. By contrast, a bundle is said to be univalent if every other bundle is a pullback of it in at most one way (up to homotopy). In the language of (∞,1)-category theory, a univalent bundle is an object classifier.
The univalence axiom does not literally say that anything is univalent in this sense. However, it is equivalent to saying that the canonical fibration over is univalent: every fibration with small fibers is an essentially unique pullback of this one (while those with large fibers are not, they are pullbacks of the next higher ). For a description of this equivalence, see section 4.8 of the HoTT Book (syntactically) and Gepner-Kock (semantically).
Univalence is a commonly assumed axiom in homotopy type theory, and is central to the proposal (Voevodsky) that this provides a natively homotopy theoretic foundation of mathematics (see at univalent foundations for mathematics).
We work in a dependent type theory with identity types, function types, dependent product types, product types, and dependent sum types.
There are multiple notions of equivalence types in dependent type theory, which can be used for a definition of univalence for a type universe ; these include
Let us assume an arbitrary notion of equivalence type . Every Russell universe is a reflexive graph with the graph type family defined as and the function is defined as
Similarly, every Tarski universe with universal type family is a reflexive graph with the graph type family defined as and the function is defined as
And finally, every Tarski universe with type of terms and function is a reflexive graph with the graph type family defined as
and the function is defined as
Now, let us assume an arbitrary notion of equivalence type . A Russell or Tarski universe is univalent if it is univalent as a reflexive graph, or equivalently, if one of the following equivalent conditions by the fundamental theorem of identity types hold:
That for each the type of elements such that is a contractible type.
That there is a family of equivalences
That is an identity system.
That for each and , the function is an equivalence of types
That is a retraction (This is due to Daniel Licata in Licata 16)
That with the function satisfies the universal property of the unary sum of .
See fundamental theorem of identity types for proofs that these definitions are the same.
Traditional homotopy type theory uses the type of functions with contractible fibers for both and , while Mike Shulman‘s model of higher observational type theory uses the type of -small one-to-one correspondences for and the type of definitional isomorphisms for .
There are stricter versions of univalence, where we replace the equivalence of types between the identity type and the type of equivalences of the universe in the univalence axioms with some notion of equality, such as judgmental equality, propositional equality, and typal equality.
In any dependent type theory with judgmental equality, given a type universe , one could replace the equivalence of types in the definition of univalence with a judgmental equality of types. This results in judgmental univalence, which states that for all small types and , one could judge that .
Similarly, in the context of any logic over type theory with propositional equality, given a type universe , one could replace the equivalence of types in the definition of univalence with a propositional equality of types. This results in propositional univalence, which states that for all small types and , .
Finally, if we are working inside a Tarski universe , then given an internal Tarski universe with , one could replace the equivalence of types in the definition of univalence with a typal equality of types. This results in typal univalence, which states that for all small types and , there is an identification .
Each of these imply the usual versions of univalence either through the structural rules for judgmental equality and propositional equality, or through identification elimination, transport, and action on identifications for typal equality.
With judgmentally univalent Tarski universes , identities are equivalences of types and . Namely, given function types and the isEquiv type family, one could add rules to the type theory which says that behaves as an equivalence type:
Introduction rules:
Elimination rules:
Computation rules:
Uniqueness rules:
In the context of function extensionality, Ian Orton and Andrew Pitts showed here that the univalence axiom can be simplified to the following special cases:
The proof constructs (for ) as the composite
and uses and to compute that , hence by function extensionality .
This is weaker than univalence because in the absense of function extensionality, it is no longer possible to prove univalence from this set of axioms.
In addition, unlike the definitions above, this definition of univalence cannot be generalized to reflexive graphs.
Suppose the Tarski universe has
We assume the weakest notion of Tarski universe, where the type reflection of each is only equivalent to the external type, since (judgmentally, propositionally, typally) strict Tarski universes are weakly Tarski universes, because the judgmental equality and propositional equality imply equivalence of types by the structural rules for judgmental and propostional equality, and typal equality in a type universe of types imply equivalence of types by identification elimination, transport, and action on identifications.
This allows us to define the internal type of equivalences , internal to the universe , which comes with a canonical equivalence of types
This implies that the equivalence is -small, and transport being an equivalence then implies that in any universe which is closed under function types, dependent product types, and dependent sum types, for all and , the identity type is -small.
The internal univalence axiom states that the canonical function
is an equivalence of types
This is not definable for strongly predicative type universes, since strongly predicative type universes are by definition not closed under dependent product types.
In addition, the internal and external versions of univalence imply each other. In order to show that the two axioms imply each other, we need to show that there is an identification
for all identifications . By the J rule it is enough to show that maps the identity equivalence of to the identity equivalence in . Since the identity equivalence in is just the identity function the above statement is always true. Thus, if the universe is closed under identity types, dependent product types, and dependent sum types the two univalence axioms imply each other and both define the same notion of univalent universe.
Let be a locally cartesian closed model category in which all objects are cofibrant.
By the categorical semantics of homotopy type theory, a dependent type
corresponds to a morphism in that is a fibration between fibrant objects.
Then the dependent function type
is interpreted as the internal hom in the slice category after extending to the context by pulling back along the two projections , respectively. Hence this is interpreted as
Consider then the diagonal morphism in as an object of . We would like to define a morphism
in . By the defining (product internal hom)-adjunction, it suffices to define a morphism
in . But now by the universal property of pullback, it suffices to define just in a morphism
And since the composite pullback along either composite
is the identity, both and are isomorphic to ; thus here we can take the identity morphism.
Now, using the path object factorization in
by an acyclic cofibration followed by a fibration, we obtain a fibrant replacement of in the slice model category .
Since also is fibrant by the axioms on the locally cartesian closed model category , we have a lift in the diagram in
This lift is the interpretation of the path induction that deduces a map on all paths from one on just the identity paths .
Finally, let be the subobject on the weak equivalences (…), and observe that and factor through this to give a morphism
The fibration is univalent in if this morphism is a weak equivalence. By the 2-out-of-3 property, of course, it is equivalent to ask that be a weak equivalence.
(…)
We specialize the general discussion above to the realization in sSet, equipped with the standard model structure on simplicial sets.
For any fibration (Kan fibration) between fibrant objects (Kan complexes), consider first the simplicial set
defined as the internal hom in the slice category .
Notice that the vertices of this simplicial set over a fixed pair of vertices in form the set of morphisms between the fibers in .
This is because – by the defining property of the internal hom in the slice and using that products in are pullbacks in – the horizontal morphisms of simplcial sets in
correspond bijectively to the horizontal morphisms in
in , which are precisely morphisms .
Let then
be the full sub-simplicial set on those vertices that correspond to weak equivalences ((weak) homotopy equivalences).
By a similar consideration, one sees that the diagonal morphism in , regarded as an object , comes with a canonical morphism
The fibration is univalent, precisely when this morphism is a weak equivalence.
This appears originally as Voevodsky, def. 3.4
(…)
See (Shulman 12, UF 13)
(…)
The univalence axiom implies function extensionality.
A commented version of a formal proof of this fact can be found in (Bauer-Lumsdaine).
In this section we assume that the universe is a Tarski universe. Axiom K states that for all the type is a set. This means the type reflection of the internal equivalences is an h-set, and the univalence axiom then implies that is an h-groupoid.
It is frequently stated that the univalence axiom and axiom K are inconsistent with each other. However, this is only true if the Tarski universe has internal univalent Tarski universes where the type has terms such that is an h-set which is not an h-proposition, such as the booleans type. As a result, can be proven to not be a set, causing axiom K for to be inconsistent with the existence of and univalence.
The univalence axiom is consistent with excluded middle. This is because the principle of excluded middle as traditionally defined in mathematics is about propositions or (-1)-truncated types.
The semantics of dependent type theory with excluded middle and universes satisfying the univalence axiom are boolean -toposes.
However, there is a global choice axiom which is inconsistent with univalence:
This is sometimes called “excluded middle” in the propositions as types interpretation of type theory, where the principle of excluded middle is reinterpreted so that types are used instead of mere propositions. But this choice principle is a much stronger axiom than excluded middle, being of comparable strength to a choice operator and implying that every type is an h-set; hence inconsistent with the univalence axiom.
It is currently open whether the univalence axiom enjoys canonicity in general, but for the special case of 1-truncated homotopy types (groupoids) (and two nested univalent universes and function extensionality), homotopy canonicity has been shown in (Shulman 12, section 13. Thus, in univalent homotopy 1-type theory with two universes, every term of type of the natural numbers is propositionally equal to a numeral.
The construction in (Shulman 12, section 13) uses Artin gluing of a suitable type-theoretic fibration category with the category Set and Grpd, respectively, effectively inducing canonicity from these categories. By (Shulman 12, remark 13.13) for this construction to generalize to untruncated univalent type theory, one seems to need a sufficiently strict global sections functor with values in some model for infinity-groupoids. A proof of the full result has been announced by Christian Sattler and Krzysztof Kapulkin (Sattler 19).
Notice that this sort of canonicity does not yet imply computational effectiveness?, which would require also an algorithm to extract that numeral from the given term. There may be such an algorithm, but so far attempts to extract one from the proof (or to give a constructive version of the proof, which would imply the existence of an algorithm) have not succeeded.
It is also a propositional canonicity, as opposed to the judgmental canonicity which many traditional type theories enjoy. Another approach to canonicity for 1-truncated univalence can be found in (Harper-Licata), which involves modifying the type theory by adding more judgmental equalities, resulting in a judgmental canonicity. However, no algorithm for computing canonical forms has yet been given for this approach either.
Canonicity has been proved for cubical type theory.
One might also try to construct the Hoffman-Streicher groupoid model in a constructive framework; Awodey and Bauer have done some work in this direction with an impredicative universe of h-sets.
In a post to the Homotopy Type Theory Google Group, Peter LeFanu Lumsdaine wrote:
Let be any pointed type, and be a universe (with rules as I set out a couple of emails ago). Then is again a universe, admitting all the same constructors as : take
,
,and so on; that is, constructor operations on are constantly on the first component, and mirror those of on the second component.
Now if is univalent, and has non-trivial (e.g. ), then ) gives a univalent universe sitting inside a non-univalent one (again, with the rules as I set out earlier).
Slightly more generally, given any cumulative pair of universes , we can consider ; this shows we can additionally have the smaller universe represented by an element of the larger one.
[N]ot only is not univalent, it’s not even “univalent on the image of ”, as was the case for the example in the groupoid model that I mentioned.
In dependent type theory with type variables, presented using a single type judgment and with identity types between types, it is possible to state the univalence axiom without any type universes.
The univalence axiom states that the function
inductively defined by
is an equivalence of types for all types and ,
where is the identity function on the type . This is given by the following axiom:
In impredicative polymorphism, this is also given by the following axiom:
Unlike the other presentation of dependent type theory in terms of universes, in this presentation of dependent type theory with a type judgment and type variables, it is consistent to assume both the univalence axiom and an axiom of set truncation like UIP or axiom K, since here there is no universe.
Univalence is closely related to the “completeness” condition in the theory of Segal spaces/semi-Segal spaces. See complete Segal space/_complete semi-Segal space.
contrary to univalence is the axiom UIP
For more references see also at homotopy type theory.
Arguably, the earliest occurrence of a version of the univalence axiom is due – under the name “universe extensionality” – to:
Strictly speaking, univalence for propositions has a much longer pedigree, this that can and does hold even in set-level foundations, but this is the earliest version of univalence that goes beyond what is possible there. However, their universe extensionality axiom is stated only for h-sets, and would be incorrect if naively generalized to higher types. The correct statement that works for higher types requires a better definition of equivalences in homotopy type theory (see there for details), which Voevodsky was the first to give.
For comments on the early history see also:
It is this notion of equivalence in homotopy type theory which was fixed in
ever since the univalence axiom is widely attributed to Voevodsky. Earlier documentation of the univalence axiom in modern form is hard to come by:
The first technical understanding of (the semantics of) univalence in simplicial sets seems to be due to:
(which 6 years later came to be written up as Kapulkin, Lumsdaine & Voevodsky12 and another 10 years later was published as Kapulkin & Lumsdaine 2021).
The first mentioning by Voevodsky of the term “univalence” by email is 3.5 years later, from Dec. 30 2009 (according to Grayson, Oct. 2017).
The earliest recorded statement of the univalence axiom by Voevodsky’s hand date may be Voevodsky (2010), p. 11
see also:
Later in:
appears the claim that:
have been working on the ideas that led to the discovery of univalent models since 2005 and gave the first public presentation on this subject at Ludwig-Maximilians-Universität München in November 2009.
A comprehensive discussion finally appears in the textbook:
Voevodsky’s (Bousfield’s) original idea for the universal Kan fibration as a model for a univalent universe in simplicial sets/-groupoids was eventually published as:
Exposition and survey
Peter Aczel, On Voevodsky’s Univalence Axiom, talk at Third European Set Theory Conference (2011) [pdf, pdf]
(in view of the structure identity principle)
Mike Shulman, Homotopy type theory, IV (blog post)
Additional definition of univalent universes appeared in section 17.1 of
as well as in this Google Groups thread:
An accessible account of Voevodsky’s proof (following Bousfield 06) that the universal Kan fibration in simplicial sets is univalent:
A quick elegant proof of the object classifier/universal associated infinity-bundle in simplicial sets/-groupoids is in
See also
Implementation of univalence in proof assistants:
in Agda:
in Coq:
A guided walk through the formal proof that univalence implies functional extensionality is at
Some details regarding the univalence axiom for weakly Tarski universes appeared on MathOverflow in:
A discussion of univalence in categories of diagrams over an inverse category with values in a category for which univalence is already established is discussed in
This discusses canonicity of univalence in its section 13. Another approach to showing canonicity is (via cubical sets) in
A proof of canonicity is presented in the talk
On the issue of strict pullback of the univalent universe see
The computational interpretation of univalence / canonicity is discussed in
Dan Licata, Robert Harper, Computing with Univalence (2012) (pdf)
Robert Harper, Daniel Licata, Canonicity for 2-dimensional type theory (2011) (pdf)
Daniel LicataThe computational interpretation of HoTT (in 2D), talk at UF-IAS-2012 (video)
Simon Huber (with Thierry Coquand), Towards a computational justification of the Axiom of Univalence , talk at TYPES 2011 (pdf)
Bruno Barras, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber, A Generalization of Takeuti-Gandy Interpretation (pdf)
and realized in cubical type theory in
Thierry Coquand (with Marc Bezem and Simon Huber), Computational content of the Axiom of Univalence, September 2013 (pdf)
Cyril Cohen, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber, Anders Mörtberg, Cubical Type Theory: a constructive interpretation of the univalence axiom (pdf)
Marc Bezem, Thierry Coquand, Simon Huber, The univalence axiom in cubical sets (arXiv:1710.10941)
A study of the semantic side of univalence in (infinity,1)-toposes, as well as further cases of locally cartesian closed (infinity,1)-categories is in
This does not yet show that the univalence axiom in its usual form holds in the internal type theory of (infinity,1)-toposes, however, due to the lack of a (known) sufficiently strict model for the object classifier. (But it works with Tarski universes, see there and type universes). Constructions of such a model in some very special cases are in Shulman12 above, and also in
Michael Shulman, The univalence axiom for elegant Reedy presheaves, arXiv:1307.6248.
Denis-Charles Cisinski, Univalent universes for elegant models of homotopy types (arXiv:1406.0058)
Finally, full proof that all ∞-stack (∞,1)-topos have presentations by model categories which interpret (provide categorical semantics) for homotopy type theory with univalent type universes:
Application of univalence to proof transfer:
Some discussion about the univalence axiom in dependent type theory with type variables occurs in:
Last revised on December 17, 2024 at 00:51:09. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.