A pseudo-order or strict total order or strict linear order is the irreflexive version of a total order. This is sometimes called linear order, but linear order is also used to refer to the non-strict total order.
A pseudo-ordered set or strictly totally ordered set is a set equipped with a pseudo-order.
In classical mathematics, the distinction between strict total orders and total orders is merely a terminological technicality, which is not always observed; more precisely, there is a natural bijection between the set of total orders on a given set and the set of strict total orders on , and one distinguishes them by the notation (for the strict total orders) and (for the total order). In constructive mathematics, however, they are irreducibly different.
A pseudo-order or strict total order on a set is a (binary) relation with the following properties:
In classical mathematics, one may see these versions of asymmetry and connectedness:
Using excluded middle, these are equivalent to asymmetry and connectedness as given above, but they need not hold for all pseudo-orders in constructive mathematics.
Actually, these axioms are overkill; to begin with, irreflexivity is simply a special case of asymmetry and so can be dropped. Additionally, one can either drop transitivity or drop asymmetry (which then requires keeping irreflexivity); they will still follow from the other axioms. Dropping transitivity shows manifestly the duality (see below) between pseudo-orders and total orders (even in constructive mathematics), and dropping asymmetry shows that a pseudo-order is a weakly linear strict preorder. Keeping transitivity and irreflexivity (thus allowing one to drop asymmetry) shows manifestly that a pseudo-order is a special kind of strict preorder.
Also, because the relation is asymmetric, holds, which means that the inequality relation , defined by
can equivalently be defined using the exclusive disjunction:
Thus, the connectedness axiom can be expressed using exclusive disjunction:
In classical mathematics, there are even more options. Now one can prove trichotomy: since the proposition is a decidable proposition, ( xor ) xor . Also, weak linearity can be dropped, as it follows from transitivity and connectedness.
Thus the most common definition uses only trichotomy and transitivity.
One can also interpret connectedness not as an axiom but as a definition of equality, getting a pseudo-order on a quotient set of . In other words, if is an asymmetric and weakly linear relation on , and we define to mean that neither nor , then is an equivalence relation and induces a pseudo-order on .
Classically, any total order defines an example of a pseudo-order (as explained below), and this also holds constructively in discrete mathematics. Since most pseudo-orders in these cases are usually described in terms of their total orders, the focus here is on constructive analysis. (The first item, however, is an exception.)
Using excluded middle, one can move between strict linear orders and total orders using negation; that is, the negation of a strict linear order is a total order and vice versa. Actually one usually swaps the order too, as follows:
To prove this, it's enough to see that the properties of a strict linear order are dual to the properties of a total order, as follows:
strict linear order | total order | |
---|---|---|
irreflexivity | reflexivity | |
asymmetry | totality | |
transitivity | weak linearity | |
weak linearity | transitivity | |
connectedness | antisymmetry |
Constructively, these are still the default definitions to use; that is, if one is given a strict linear order or a total order and wants to interpret the other symbol, then one does so using these definitions. However, the result will not necessarily be a total order or a strict linear order. To be specific, if one starts with a strict linear order and defines as above, then totality does not follow; and if one starts with a total order and defines as above, then weak linearity does not follow. Nevertheless, at least will be a partial order, and least will be a strict preorder. Furthermore, the duality between the axioms is still there, even though negation no longer mediates between them; although weak linearity need not hold for a total order constructively, the duality is preserved if one defines strict linear orders without using transitivity.
One often sees defined as but ; this is equivalent, but doesn't show the de Morgan duality explicitly. Similarly, one often sees defined as or ; this is not even equivalent constructively, although it is classically.
Keep in mind, however, that the only use of excluded middle in the classical theory is the assumption that , , and are always either true or false. There is therefore a perfect correspondence between decidable strict linear orders and decidable total orders on sets with decidable equality.
A pseudo-order on a set is decidable if for all and in , or .
Given a proposition , can be made into a subsingleton set by considering the subset of the singleton . Let denote the disjoint union of sets and , and let denote the function set with domain and codomain .
Every decidable pseudo-order on a set is purely cotransitive: Given elements , , and in , one can construct an element of the function set
We prove this by case analysis.
Suppose that . Then one can construct the element and by definition of disjoint union an element . is given by the constant function .
Now suppose that . This means that , and one can construct the element . By definition of disjoint union one can construct an element . is given by the constant function .
Since is decidable this covers every possible case. Thus, every decidable pseudo-order is purely cotransitive.
The above proof first appeared for the pseudo-order of the real numbers in theorem 11.4.3 of the HoTT book in the context of dependent type theory.
Suppose that the rational numbers are a subset of the decidably pseudo-ordered set , and the canonical injection is strictly monotonic. Then for every element of one can construct a locator for .
The locator is given by the dependent function
which always exists by the previous theorem and by the fact that the rational numbers are a subset of which preserves the pseudo-order.
Wikipedia, https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pseudo-order
Heyting, Arend (1966). Intuitionism: an introduction (2nd ed.). Amsterdam: North-Holland Pub. Co. p. 106. ISBN:978-0-444-53406-4
For a proof that the decidable pseudo-order on the real numbers is purely cotransitive, see theorem 11.4.3 of:
Last revised on September 25, 2024 at 22:51:49. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.