basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
The axiom of countable choice (), also called or , is a weak form of the axiom of choice; it says that the set of natural numbers is a projective object in Set. (Recall that the full axiom of choice states that every set is projective.)
In classical mathematics, countable choice is usually accepted because the full axiom of choice is accepted. In constructive mathematics the situation is more subtle. For varying reasons, some schools of constructive mathematics accept countable choice (though they reject the full axiom of choice). On the other hand, countable choice is not valid in the internal logic of a general topos, so if one desires this level of generality then it should not be assumed. There are also philosophical constructivist arguments against it. Fred Richman (RichmanFTA) has said that
Countable choice is a blind spot for constructive mathematicians in much the same way as excluded middle is for classical mathematicians.
All the reasoning in this page is constructive.
More explicitly, let be any set and let be a surjection. Then the axiom of countable choice states that has a section. If you phrase the axiom of choice in terms of entire relations, then countable choice states that any entire relation from to any other set contains (in the 2-poset Rel) a functional entire relation.
In dependent type theory, countable choice says that the dependent product of a family of inhabited sets indexed by the natural numbers is itself inhabited:
Alternatively, the axiom of countable choice states that given a family of sets indexed by natural numbers and a family of propositions indexed by natural numbers and element , if for all natural numbers there merely exists an element such that , then there merely exists a dependent function such that for all natural numbers , :
Here we collect some consequences of the countable axiom of choice.
The Cauchy real numbers and Dedekind real numbers coincide (the law of excluded middle also separately implies this).
The Rosolini dominance is a dominance (the law of excluded middle also separately implies this).
Unlike the full axiom of choice, countable choice is often considered to be a constructively acceptable principle. In particular, it does not imply the principle of excluded middle. It is a consequence of COSHEP. A stronger version of countable choice, also a consequence of , is the axiom of dependent choice (). In general, is enough to justify results in analysis involving sequences.
Sometimes in foundations it is useful to consider a weaker version of countable choice, called . This states that any entire relation from to itself contains a functional entire relation, i.e. there exists a sequence in such that holds. In terms of surjections, the axiom states that any surjection has a section if is a subset of and is the restriction to of a product projection. is enough to prove that every Dedekind real number is a Cauchy real number (the converse is always true).
The axiom of weak countable choice () states that a surjection has a section if, whenever , at least one of the preimages and is a singleton. follows (for different reasons) from either or excluded middle. On the other hand, is enough to prove that the fundamental theorem of algebra in the sense that every non-constant complex polynomial has a root; see Bridges et al (1998). It is an open question whether implies that the Dedekind reals and Cauchy reals coincide, see King et al (2024).
An axiom variously called and is countable choice for subsets of ; that is, every -indexed sequence of inhabited subsets of has a choice function. Like above, this also follows from either or excluded middle. It is enough to prove the equivalence of the Dedekind reals and Cauchy reals. See Saving et al (2021), King et al (2024).
An even weaker form of countable choice was proposed by Martin Escardo; it states that any surjection of the form has a section, where is a decidable subset and is an arbitrary set with the projection. This follows from WCC and also from the limited principle of omniscience; see the constructivenews discussion.
One easy example is the category , the sheaves on the unit interval, since in that topos the Dedekind real numbers and the Cauchy real numbers are not isomorphic, and this is a consequence of the internal countable choice.
Discussion here.
To formulate a version of the axiom of countable choice in a higher category, one has to make an appropriate choice of the meaning of “epimorphism”. In most cases, it is best to choose effective epimorphism in an (infinity,1)-category or a related notion such as eso morphisms.
There are multiple version of the axiom of countable choice, depending on what truncation requirements, if any, are applied to the domain.
These are stronger axioms as increases.
There are also “internal” versions of these axioms.
In homotopy type theory (the internal logic of an -topos), the internal version of is “every surjection onto the natural numbers type with -type fibers has a section”, or equivalently
More generally, we can replace the -truncation by the -truncation to obtain a family of axioms .
We can also replace the -truncation by the assertion of -connectedness, obtaining the axiom of countable -connected choice.
Fred Richman, Douglas Bridges, Peter Schuster, A weak countable choice principle. Proceedings of the American Mathematical Society 128(9):2749-2752, March 2000. [doi:10.1090/S0002-9939-00-05327-2]
Martin Escardo et. al., Special case of countable choice, message and discussion to the constructivenews list, google groups
Fred Richman, The fundamental theorem of algebra: a constructive development without choice. Pacific Journal of Mathematics 196 1 (2000) 213–230 [doi:10.2140/pjm.2000.196.213, pdf]
Mark Saving et al (2021). A weak form of countable choice. MathOverflow.
Christopher King et al (2024). Does weak countable choice imply that the Cauchy reals are Dedekind complete? MathOverflow.
See also
Last revised on December 6, 2024 at 20:20:55. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.