This page is about the notion in combinatorics. For other notions of the same name see at graph of a function and graph of a functor.
A graph is a collection of vertices and edges; each edge links a pair of vertices, defining a relationship of incidence between vertices and edges. There are several variations on the idea, described below.
This is the sense of graph in combinatorics; the other sense in high-school algebra, which interprets a morphism as a subobject of the product , is unrelated; see graph of a function for more on this.
Let and be sets; call an element of a vertex and an element of an edge. A graph is given by , , and a mapping that interprets edges as pairs of vertices. Exactly what this means depends on how one defines ‘mapping that interprets’ and ‘pair’; the possibilities are given below. We will need the following notation:
We are now ready for the first batch of definitions.
For a simple graph, a pair of vertices is a subset of of cardinality , and we interpret edges as unordered pairs of vertices in a one-to-one way. Thus a simple graph is given by , , and an injective function . Among graph theorists, this is often the default meaning of ‘graph’ unless another is specified. The category of simple graphs is called SimpGph
For a multigraph, a pair of vertices is the same as above, but we interpret edges as pairs of vertices in a many-to-one way. Thus a multigraph is given by , , and an arbitrary function .
For a loop graph, a pair of vertices is any subset of the form , where is allowed, and we interpret edges as pairs of vertices in a one-to-one way again. Thus a loop-graph is given by , , and an injective function .
For a pseudograph, a pair of vertices is as in a loop graph, while edges are interpreted as pairs of vertices as in a multigraph. Thus a pseudograph is given by , , and a function .
Note: While ‘simple graph’ is unambiguous, the other terms above are not. In particular, ‘multigraph’ sometimes means a pseudograph, ‘pseudograph’ sometimes means a loop graph, and ‘loop graph’ sometimes means a pseudograph. These could be made unambiguous by saying ‘simple multigraph’, ‘simple loop graph’, and ‘multipseudograph’, respectively, but we will try to keep our terminology short. An oldfashioned (e.g. p. 142) term for ‘simple graph’ is ‘linear graph’, traces of which remain in the usual term ‘linear hypergraph’ in combinatorics (i.e. hypergraph any two edges of which intersect in at most one element of the ground set).
In all four of the above, edges are interpreted as unordered pairs. If we instead interpret edges as ordered pairs, then we get four new concepts:
Directed pseudographs are commonly used in category theory, where they are often called ‘directed graphs’, ‘digraphs’, or (less ambiguously) ‘quivers’.
The same terminological ambiguities as above apply here as well, and they can be resolved in the same way, including using ‘simple directed graph’ for a directed graph if necessary. One can also use ‘undirected’ in place of ‘directed’ to emphasise that the previous definitions apply instead of these.
It is always possible to interpret any kind of graph as a directed pseudograph (a quiver), in which there happens to be at most one edge between a given pair of vertices, or there happen to be no loops (or alternatively exactly one of every possible kind of loop), or in which there is an edge from to if and only if there is an edge from to , or some mixture of these.
There is an alternative definition of an undirected graph allowing loops and multiple edges (cf. Serre 1977), that begins with the structure of a quiver and then asks in addition for a fixed point free involution on edges swapping source and target, i.e., such that
Of course, since the source and target functions determine each other in the presence of the involution , it is enough to give, say, and to define an undirected graph. In that case, one might alternatively view as a set of “half-edges” or “flags” (with the involution swapping the two halves of an edge), and even lift the condition that has no fixed points to allow for the possibility of undirected graphs with “dangling” or “open” edges (i.e., with only one side attached to a vertex).
Although this definition of undirected graphs with open edges is standard (cf. ribbon graph), Kock (2016b) remarks that “it does not naturally lead to good notions of morphisms, beyond isomorphisms”. A slight variation of this definition with a more natural notion of morphism was introduced by Joyal and Kock (2009): they define a “Feynman graph” as a triple of finite sets together with a triple of a function , an injection , and a fixed point free involution . (See also Kock (2016a) for further discussion.)
An orientation of an undirected graph is the choice of a direction for every edge. Formally, if we define undirected graphs as above to be quivers equipped with a fixed point free involution , then an orientation corresponds to the choice of a subset such that is the disjoint union .
Any orientation of an undirected graph induces a corresponding directed graph . In many situations, though, it is useful to consider a given undirected graph equipped with one of many possible orientations. For example, various graph invariants? (such as the flow polynomial?, or Tutte‘s original definition of the Tutte polynomial?) can be defined for an arbitrary orientation of a graph, but are independent of the choice of orientation.
The term arc is often used for an ordered edge, while line is sometimes used for an unordered edge. We say that an arc with is an arc from to , while a line such that is a line between and . In either case, a loop is an edge from a vertex to itself or between a vertex and itself; only (possibly directed) loop graphs and pseudographs can have loops.
Given any sort of graph, we can define a binary relation on ; say that and are adjacent, written , if there exists an edge such that or . A directed loop graph is determined entirely by this relation; we may say that it is equipped with a binary relation. Then a simple directed graph is equipped with an irreflexive relation (or equivalently a reflexive relation), and an undirected loop graph is equipped with a symmetric relation.
A graph is finite if and are both finite sets. Given a linear ordering of the vertices of a finite graph, its adjacency matrix is a square matrix whose th entry gives the number of edges between the th and th vertices or from the th vertex to the th vertex. In the examples above where a graph is determined by a binary relation on , then matrix multiplication gives composition of relations.
An isomorphism from to consists of a bijection , together with a bijection from to (also denoted ) such that commutes with ; that is, or whenever or (as appropriate). Two graphs and are isomorphic if there exists such an isomorphism. Then finite graphs and are isomorphic if and only if they have the same number of vertices and, for some ordering of their vertices, they have the same adjacency matrix.
A morphism from to should consist of functions and such that commutes with . However, some authors allow to be undefined if or but when using a notion of graph where loops are forbidden. The difference amounts to whether one interprets a simple graph as a special kind of loop graph in which no loops exist (the first kind of morphism) or in which each vertex has a unique loop (the second kind of morphism). Either way, an isomorphism (as defined above) is precisely an invertible morphism.
Under the second notion of morphism (where simple graphs are identified with sets equipped with a symmetric reflexive relation), the category of simple graphs has many desirable properties (q.v.).
A usual definition of subgraph in combinatorics is, roughly: subset. More precisely, if undirected simple graph means pair of two sets, with any subset of the set of all two-element subsets of , then a usual meaning of subgraph of is (cf. e.g. p. 3): any pair with , , and1 .
In particular, such a subgraph may have isolated vertices which are not isolated in the ambient graph , and need not be an induced subgraph, which by definition is a subgraph in the above sense for which . In words: the edge-set of an induced subgraph must contain all edges induced within the ambient graph by the vertex set of the subgraph.2
Another usual notion of subgraph in combinatorics is3 spanning subgraph:
this means just any subgraph in the above sense with . There are three kinds of spanning subgraphs which are the most studied: Hamilton circuits?4, perfect matchings? and spanning trees?.
From the nPOV, it is often possible to describe notions of subgraph in terms of types of monomorphisms in categories of graphs; for example,
subgraphs are monos, and
induced subgraphs are regular monos
in the category of simple graphs, and similarly for suitable categories of other types of graph.
One synonym, in the nLab5 for induced subgraph is full subgraph, for brevity, and for harmony with other uses of full in category theory (but also for more precise reasons).
The precise meaning of subgraph depends on the chosen formalization of graph, needless to say.
Recall that a simplicial complex of dimension one consists of the data of a set together with a set of non-empty subsets of of cardinality at most , that contains all of the singleton subsets. In other words, a 1-dimensional simplicial complex is essentially the same thing as a simple graph, with the set of edges being determined by the set of simplices and vice versa:
For this reason, simple graphs are sometimes referred to as simplicial graphs (Gross & Tucker 1987). On the other hand, an undirected graph with loops or multiple edges can more generally be seen as a 1-dimensional CW-complex (or more precisely, it has a geometric realization as a CW-complex in which 0-cells correspond to vertices and 1-cells to edges).
Given a general undirected graph, it is always possible to obtain a simple graph through the process of barycentric subdivision. Let be a graph with vertex set and edge set . The barycentric subdivision of is the graph with vertex set , and with an edge joining to just in case is incident to (i.e., at either end of) in . It is easy to check that contains no loops, while the two-fold barycentric subdivision contains no loops or multiple edges, in other words is a simple graph. (More generally, the -fold barycentric subdivision contains no circuit of length ). Part of the reason for the importance of simple graphs is that many “topological” properties of a graph (such as planarity, first Betti number, etc., which can be defined in terms of the geometric realization of ) are preserved under barycentric subdivision. (Although obviously, not all graph-theoretic properties are preserved. For example, barycentric subdivision always produces a bipartite graph).
At the Como conference in 1990, William Lawvere gave a videotaped lecture including the following remarks:
I have great problems reading books on graph theory, books and papers on graph theory, because they never tell you exactly what they are talking about. Sometimes the graphs are [word inaudible, even when played slower], sometimes they are absolutely reflexive, sometimes they are not. Even if they go so far as talking about homomorphisms, I still don’t know exactly what that is, i.e., which category are we in? What they should do is admit that they are working in three or four different categories and they don’t know how to pass from one to the other, and so on, and [inaudible words] to simplify.
But no, they prefer to talk in a vague way and smushing these together. [inaudible] tried to understand some of the problems of graph theorists and get [bogged? locked?] in the first page. Does anybody actually know what a graph minor is? [some interjection from the audience] Graph minor. Big problem. (..) you see, this famous [inaudible works] problem on graph minors. Looks like that that might be interesting. But I can’t determine exactly what it is, because, if you read the first parts of the paper, they waffle, you see, they don’t give you a property (…) ([William Lawvere] in his 1990 lecture at Como, Italy, Villa Olmo)
The notion of graph bifurcates in constructive mathematics:
The set of edges of a graph could be defined with a denial inequality:
The set of edges of a graph could be defined with a tight apartness relation:
Textbooks:
Frank Harary (1969), Graph Theory, Addison-Wesley.
Frank Harary and E.M. Palmer (1973), Graphical Enumeration, Academic Press.
Jean-Pierre Serre (1977), Trees, Springer.
W. T. Tutte (1984), Graph Theory, Addison-Wesley.
Jonathan L. Gross and Thomas W. Tucker (1987), Topological Graph Theory, Wiley.
Gunther Schmidt and Thomas Ströhlein (1993), Relations and Graphs: Discrete Mathematics for Computer Scientists, EATCS Monographs on Theoretical Computer Science, Springer.
A. Bondy. Basic Graph Theory: Paths and Circuits. Elsevier Amsterdam, 1995, Vol. 1, pp. 1–110
Chris Godsil and Gordon Royle (2001), Algebraic Graph Theory, Springer.
Reinhard Diestel, Graph Theory, Graduate Texts in Mathematics 173 5th edition (2017) [website, doi:10.1007/978-3-662-53622-3]
Teo Banica. Graphs and their symmetries (2024). (arXiv:2406.03664).
Other references:
Bill Lawvere (1989), Qualitative distinctions between some toposes of generalized graphs, in Categories in computer science and logic (Boulder, CO, 1987), volume 92 of Contemporary Mathematics, 261–299. American Mathematical Society, Providence, RI.
E. Babson, H. Barcelo, M. de Longueville, R. Laubenbacher, A Homotopy Theory for Graphs, arXiv:math/0403146
Ronnie Brown, I. Morris, J. Shrimpton, and C.D. Wensley (2008), Graphs of Morphisms of Graphs, Electronic Journal of Combinatorics, A1 of Volume 15(1), 1–28.
Frank Harary?: On the notion of balance of a signed graph. The Michigan Mathemathical Journal, Volume 2, Issue 2 (1953), 143-146.
André Joyal and Joachim Kock, Feynman graphs, and nerve theorem for compact symmetric multicategories (extended abstract), in Proceedings of the 6th International Workshop on Quantum Physics and Logic(Oxford 2009), Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 270 (2) (2011), 105-113. arXiv:0908.2675
Joachim Kock, Graphs, hypergraphs, and properads, Collect. Math. 67 (2016), 155-190. arXiv:1407.3744
Joachim Kock, Cospan construction of the graph category of Borisov and Manin, arXiv:1611.10342
Martin Schmidt, Functorial Approach to Graph and Hypergraph Theory, (arXiv:1907.02574)
See also quiver - references.
Discussion of use of simplicial complexes in graph theory:
The last condition is to ensure that is itself again a graph, which would not be guaranteed if we defined subgraph to be just any pair of subsets of the respective sets and . ↩
This happens to be the usual notion of substructure in model theory, for any relational structure. ↩
Somewhat counterintuitively (with regard to connotations of the words spanning and induced), a spanning subgraph need not be induced, and in fact it never is, except if the subgraph is the graph itself. ↩
We here follow A. Bondy’s choice of words in p. 20, both in the decision whether to use hamiltonian or Hamilton, and whether to use cycle or circuit. The term circuit is less usual than cycle in combinatorics, but less ambiguous, not longer, and more clearly signalling that the combinatorial notion is meant (not one of the many other meanings of cycle). One argument in favor of Hamilton is that any circuit, by itself, is hamiltonian. ↩
Incidentally, the term full was in use in mid-twentieth century graph theory, then seems to have fallen out of favor. ↩
Last revised on June 7, 2024 at 11:23:46. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.