previous chapter: motivation for sheaves, cohomology and higher stacks
home: sheaves and stacks
next chapter: presheaf categories with values in small sets
Urs, do you want comments here? I mean that, besides fixing typos and noting out-and-out mistakes, would you like me to make a note if I think that something you've said is poorly explained, or an unjustified conclusion, or so on? —Toby
Sure, I’d appreciate it. – Urs
The theme of this chapter is the fundamental concept category.
Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets, ;
we list some important constructions and examples in this context
we end by characterizing equivalence of categories:
every category has a skeleton: an equivalent category in which all isomorphic objects are equal;
a functor between categories is an equivalence precisely if it is
the next chapter then defines “categories of small sets” and categories of functors with values in these: presheaves
We need the language of category theory in order to talk about sheaves. This language is very fundamental to mathematics, so much that in the course of setting it up one has to consider foundational issues: all of mathematics is supposed to be chain of rigorous deduction, but some very basic concepts need to be assumed be be universally understood by grace, and all deduction is based on these universally understood concepts.
This basic concept has traditionally be taken to be that of a collection of elements – a set – with a global binary relation – – that determines which sets are elements of other sets. Naïve and obvious as it may seem, there is famously some subtlety hidden here, related to the global nature of the inclusion relation.
After the advent of category theory it was realized by Lawvere and others, that, roughly, what is truly fundamental is not so much the concept of a set itself, but rather the interrelation between sets in terms of the functions between them. The behaviour of these functions is axiomatized by saying that they form the Category of Sets, denoted . This notion is the fundamental elementary notion for all the following development: all further constructions take place inside .
One advantage of this perspective is that it allows to naturally address and handle concerns and disagreement about what actually does count as naive and universally accepted basis of all reasoning. This is because the crucial property of the Category of Sets is that it is a topos: a “place” in which mathematics may be developed. When one strictly sticks to constructions within SET, as opposed to, say, the traditional Zermelo-Fraenkel axiomatics for set theory, then essentially all constructions and results make sense internal to any other topos. For instance constructivism is a school of thought which asserts that some axioms about naïve sets are not quite naïve enough and reject them, notably the axiom of excluded middle. This point of view turns out to be perfectly compatible, and in fact enforced, by the topos-theoretic perspective on foundations.
In setting up the concept we will deal with elementary concepts in category theory such as category, product, coproduct etc. in a naïve fashion: these constructions are formulated in terms of collections of entities such as “arrows” or “functions” in a way that is supposed to be “universally understood by grace”, very analogous to the way traditional Zermelo-Fraenkel axiomatics assumes that it is “universally understood by grace” what it means for an entity to be element of some set. It is in a second step, when we systematically set up category theory internal to that these constructions appear again in terms of formal definitions inside itself, or more precisely inside of universes in .
The Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets – ETCS for short – is a “structural” formalization of set theory which combines the rich tradition of naïve (= pre-axiomatic) set theory with the insights of category theory;
literature:
Lawvere and Rosebrugh: Sets for Mathematics, Cambridge University Press
ETCS differs from non-structural material set theory in the way it handles the membership relation :
in ETCS “sets” and “elemens” are of different type: not every element of a set is necessarily a set itself;
no element exists in isolation: it always exists relative to the set that it is an element of.
a notion of generalized element that comes with its domain of definition plays a crucial role: such generalized elements are just another perspective on functions between sets – called morphisms in – and these functions are taken to be the primary concept, while the ordinary notion of an ordinary element of a set is a derived concept;
this is a general category theoretic perspective: what matters is the relational structure encoded in the morphisms , and not any imagined “inner structure” of the objects , :
this inner structure, the the extent that it makes sense to speak of it, is determined by the behaviour of the morphisms.
in techical terms, which will not concern us further for the time being, the Categroy of Sets to be described now is
a topos;
which is well-pointed;
satisfies the axiom of choice;
and is equipped with a natural numbers object
Now the definition.
SET consists of
a collection of “objects” called “sets” and usually denoted by capital letters, often from the middle of the alphabet ;
a collection of “arrows” called “morphisms” or “functions” that go between pairs of objects, denoted etc.
a composition operation on all pairs of composable morphisms;
such that the associativity law is respected: composition of any three composable morphisms is uniquely defined;
such that the morphisms of the form are units with respect to this compositon: ;
Remark to those readers who already know categories: So far this would say that SET is a category: but the point is that we take the above as a primitive notion and avoid saying “it is a category with a set/class of objects, etc.”. Rather, ETCS is thought of as having a “collection” of objects in a pre-axiomatic sense. The possibly familiar notion of a small or large
category appears below as a concept internal to SET.
Notation
A function we also call an element of with domain (or “stage of definition” ).
If we allow ourselves to denote comopsition simply by juxtaposition then for a function and another function regarded as an element of over domain of definition , the notation denotes consistently both the composition of two functions and the application of the function to the element .
Terminology and further concepts
monomorphism if for every
and , implies .
In different but equivalent language: a function is injective if for all elements over the same domain, implies .
A morphism is an
epimorphism if for every
and the condition implies .
In different but equivalent language: a function is surjective if it is a monomorphism.
a morphism is an isomorphism if there exists a morphism such that and .
After the defining properties on are imposed in the following section, all these notions will reproduce their expected familar meaning.
set theory, strictly speaking
every element in the language of ETCS is element only of one single set.
The above structure of SET is required to satisfy the following axioms.
Axiom of products.
This means first of all: For any two sets , there is a set and functions , , such that given two elements over the same domain, there exists a unique element over that domain for which
Notice that the crucial condition is that exists and exists uniquely. This witnesses the universal property of the product.
A choice of product is usually denoted . To make a bridge with naive set-theory notation, we may suggestively write
where the funny equality sign and bracketing notation on the right simply mean that the cartesian product is uniquely defined up to isomorphism by its collection of (generalized) elements, which correspond to pairs of elements.
Moreover, admitting finite products also means that the empty product exists: there is an object in Set
which has a unique element over any domain;
equivalently: such that for every other object there is a unique morphism
Notation
The above implies in particular that for two functions and there is canonically a function denoted
induced by the universal property of by from the existence of the two functions and
Axiom of equalizers.
For any two functions , there exists a function such that
Equivalently, in morphism language:
An equalizer is again defined up to isomorphism by its collection of generalized elements, denoted .
Consequence: pullbacks
The axiom of products and the axiom of equalizers already ensure that Set has pullbacks.
Given functions there exists a set and functions and such that the diagram
commutes and such that that is universal with respect to this property: for every other such diagram
there is a unique function such that
One checks that indeed is equivalently the equalizer of and :
Hence we may write
Here is the fiber product of with : over it is the product of the fibers and .
Axiom of power sets.
For every set there is a set denoted or and called the power set of and a relation to be thought of as “ is element of subset in ” so that for every relation , there exists a unique function such that is obtained up to isomorphism as the pullback
i.e the universal commutative diagram
In other words, belongs to if and only if belongs to .
Axiom of strong extensionality.
For functions
we have if and only if for all “ordinary” elements .
It is this axiom which allows to translate between the structural formulation of and other traditional ways of talking about sets.
Notice that this axiom will not hold in a general topos, only in a well-pointed topos.
Axiom of natural numbers object.
There is a set , together with an element and a function , which is initial among sets equipped with such data. That is, given a set together with an element and a function , there exists a unique function such that
in function notation
equivalently in elementwise notation, for every (generalized) element , where means .
equivalently in diagrammatic notation
Every surjective function admits a section, i.e., a function such that , the identity function.
Remark. This formulation makes the role played by the axiom of choice, which in other contexts may look a bit mysterious, quite transparent. See axiom of choice for further remarks. Notice that even if one assumes the axiom of choice in SET, it may generally fails in other topoi, and for quite natural reasons.
category is like a monoid, but with an only partially
defined composition operation: every element is assigned a source and a target object and composition is only defined if the target of one element matches the source of the other. These “elements” are then called morphisms.
directed graph equipped with a composition operation on its edges.
A functor between categories is a map of objects and of morphisms, such that all this structure is preserved. It may be thought of as a homomorphism of directed graphs which preserves the composition of morphisms.
One may also think of a category as (the fundamental category of) a directed space with morphisms the possible directed paths in that space. A functor is then thought of as a map of spaces. From this perspective a natural transformation between functors is like a homotopy between maps of spaces.
internal formulation
A category in consists of
objects of – often also denoted ;
together with
an identity assigning morphism in ;
a composition morphism in , where denotes the pullback of and ;
such that the following diagrams commute;
Here, the pullback is defined via the square
Notice that the required pullbacks here do indeed exist due to the axioms of .
in components
If we write for the set of morphisms, then we may denote the various operations above on ordinary elements on and as
source map:
target map:
identity assigning map :
composition map: .
Then
the unit laws say that
the associativity law says that for all triples of composable morphisms we have
This looks now as before in the description of itself.
further concepts and examples
general examples
concrete examples
The “classical examples” such as Set, Top, Vect etc. are discussed in the next section after the introduction of universes and small sets.
internal definition
For and cateories in as above, a functor from to in is
a morphism of objects in ;
a morphisms of morphisms in ;
such that the following diagrams commute
respect for the source map: ;
respect for the target map: ;
respect for identities ;
respect for composition .
in components
A functor maps morphisms in to morphisms in while repsecting the composition of morphisms:
concepts and examples
for , two groups, functors are group homomorphisms
a functor is necessarily essentially surjective. It gives a group isomorphism precisely if it is also full and faithful functor.
In as far as a functor is like a map of spaces, a natural transformation is like a homotopy between maps of spaces.
Another way to understand the following definition of natural transformations is to note that it follows from demanding that categories form a cartesian closed category. This is the topic of the section on monoidal categories.
internal definition
For two functors in , a natural transformation also denoted
is
a component map in
such that
in components
In terms of elements this means that for all morphisms in , the diagram
commutes.
It is helpful and turns out to make good sense to think of this square literally as a homotopy between the image path and the image path in the “space” .
examples
Since natural transformations are morphisms between functors, two functors can be different while still being isomorphic. If two functors are inverses of each other up to such natural isomorphism, their source and target categories are “the same for all practical purposes”: they are equivalent.
Definition
A functor is an equivalence of categories if there exists a functor and natural isomorphisms
and
Definition
A skeleton of a category is a category equivalent to such that all isomorphic objects in are equal.
Lemma
Every category has a skeleton which is a full subcategory .
Proof.
choose a representative object in each isomorphism class;
the full subcategory on these objects has the desired property
notice: this makes crucially use of the axiom of choice which holds in by definition
Proposition
A functor is an equivalence of categories if and only it is full and faithful and essentially surjective.
Proof.
assuming that is an equivalence, choose a weak inverse . The components of the natural isomorphism exhibit as essentially surjective, full and faithful;
assuming that is essentially surjective, full and faithful,
one finds that is an isomorphism with (strict) inverse , for and the skeleton of and respectively;
and that is a weak inverse for .
Example.
Every groupoid in that is connected (has only a single isomorphism class of objects) is equivalent to a groupoid of the form for a group: the automorphism group of any object .
Last revised on January 13, 2010 at 00:12:41. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.