nLab
proper model category

Context

Model category theory

model category

Definitions

Morphisms

Universal constructions

Refinements

Producing new model structures

Presentation of (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

Model structures

for \infty-groupoids

for ∞-groupoids

for nn-groupoids

for \infty-groups

for \infty-algebras

general

specific

for stable/spectrum objects

for (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

for stable (,1)(\infty,1)-categories

for (,1)(\infty,1)-operads

for (n,r)(n,r)-categories

for (,1)(\infty,1)-sheaves / \infty-stacks

Contents

Idea

In a model category fibrations enjoy pullback stability and cofibrations are stable under pushout, but weak equivalences need not have either property. In a proper model category weak equivalences are also preserved under certain pullbacks and/or certain pushouts.

Definition

Definition

A model category is called

  • right proper if weak equivalences are preserved by pullback along fibrations

  • left proper if weak equivalence are preserved by pushout along cofibrations

  • proper if it is both left and right proper.

Remark

More in detail this means the following. A model category is right proper if for every weak equivalence f:ABf : A \to B in WMor(C)W\subset Mor(C) and every fibration h:CBh : C \to B the pullback h *f:A× BCCh^* f : A \times_B C \to C in

A× CB A h *fW fW C hF B \array{ A \times_C B &\to& A \\ \;\;\downarrow^{\mathrlap{\Rightarrow h^* f \in W}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{f \in W}} \\ C &\stackrel{h \in F}{\to}& B }

is a weak equivalence.

Examples

Left proper model categories

Non-left proper model categories

A class of model structures which tends to be not left proper are model structures on categories of not-necessarily commutative algebras.

For instance

But it is Quillen equivalent to a model structure that is left proper. This is discussed below.

Right proper model categories

Proper model categories

Model categories which are both left and right proper include

Proper Quillen equivalent model structures

While some model categories fail to be proper, often there is a Quillen equivalent one that does enjoy properness.

Theorem

Every model category whose acyclic cofibrations are monomorphisms is Quillen equivalent to its model structure on algebraic fibrant objects. In this all objects are fibrant, so that it is right proper.

Proof

This is theorem 2.18 in

Theorem

Let TT be a simplicial (possibly multi-colored) theory, and let TAlgT Alg be the corresponding category of simplicial T-algebras. This carries a model category structure where the fibrations and weak equivalences are those of the underlying simplicial sets in the standard model structure on simplicial sets.

Then there exists a morphism of simplicial theories TST \to S such that

  1. the induced adjunction SAlgTAlgS Alg \stackrel{\to}{\leftarrow} T Alg is a Quillen equivalence;

  2. SAlgS Alg is a proper simplicial model category.

This is the content of (Rezk 00)

Properties

General

The following says that left/right properness holds locally in every model category, namely between cofibrant/fibrant objects.

Proposition

Given a model category,

  1. every pushout of a weak equivalence between cofibrant objects along a cofibration is again a weak equivalence;

  2. every pullback of a weak equivalence between fibrant objects along a fibration is again a weak equivalence.

A proof is spelled out in (Hirschhorn, prop. 13.1.2), there attributed to (Reedy).

This gives a large class of examples of left/right proper model categories:

Corollary

A model category in which all objects are cofibrant is left proper.

A model category in which all objects are fibrant is right proper.

See in the list of Examples below for concrete examples.

Homotopy (co)limits in proper model categories

Proposition

In a left proper model category, ordinary pushouts along cofibrations are homotopy pushouts.

Dually, in a right proper model category, ordinary pullbacks along fibrations are homotopy pullbacks.

Proof

This is stated for instance in HTT, prop A.2.4.4 or in prop. 1.19 in Bar. We follow the proof given in this latter reference.

We demonstrate the first statement, the second is its direct formal dual.

So consider a pushout diagram

K Y cof L X \array{ K &\to& Y \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow \\ L &\to& X }

in a left proper model category, where the morphism KLK \to L is a cofibration, as indicated. We need to exhibit a weak equivalence XXX' \stackrel{}{\to} X from an object XX' that is manifestly a homotopy pushout of LKYL \leftarrow K \to Y.

The standard procedure to produce this XX' is to pass to a weakly equivalent diagram with the property that all objects are cofibrant and one of the morphisms is a cofibration. The ordinary pushout of that diagram is well known to be the homotopy pushout, as described there.

So pick a cofibrant replacement K\emptyset \hookrightarrow K' \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} of KK and factor KKYK' \to K \to Y as a cofibration followed by a weak equivalence KYYK' \hookrightarrow Y' \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} Y and similarly factor KKLK' \to K \to L as KLLK' \hookrightarrow L' \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} L

This yields a weak equivalence of diagrams

Y Y cof K K cof cof L L, \array{ Y &\stackrel{\simeq}{\leftarrow}& Y' \\ \uparrow && \uparrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} \\ K &\stackrel{\simeq}{\leftarrow}& K' \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} \\ L &\stackrel{\simeq}{\leftarrow}& L' } \,,

where now the diagram on the right is cofibrant as a diagram, so that its ordinary pushout

X:=L KY X' := L' \coprod_{K'} Y'

is a homotopy colimit of the original diagram. To obtain the weak equivalence from there to XX, first form the further pushouts

K Y W K Y cof cof cof L X W L:=K KL L KY W L X, \array{ K &&&\to&&& Y \\ & \nwarrow^{\mathrlap{\in W}} &&&& \nearrow_{\mathrlap{\simeq}} & \\ && K' &\to& Y' && \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow \\ && L' &\to& X' && \\ & {}^{\mathllap{\in W}} \swarrow &&&& \searrow^{\mathrlap{\simeq}} & \\ L'':= K \coprod_{K'} L &&&\to&&& L'' \coprod_{K} Y \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in W}} &&&&&& \downarrow \\ L &&&\to&&& X } \,,

where the total outer diagram is the original pushout diagram. Here the cofibrations are as indicated by the above factorization and by their stability under pushouts, and the weak equivalences are as indicated by the above factorization and by the left properness of the model category. The weak equivalence LLL'' \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} L is by the 2-out-of-3 property.

This establishes in particular a weak equivalence

XL KY. X' \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} L'' \coprod_K Y \,.

It remains to get a weak equivalence further to XX. For that, take the two outer squares from the above

K Y cof L L KY W L X. \array{ K &\to& Y \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow \\ L'' &\to& L'' \coprod_{K'} Y \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in W}} && \downarrow \\ L &\to& X } \,.

Notice that the top square is a pushout by construction, and the total one by assumption. Therefore by the general theorem about pastings of pushouts, also the lower square is a pushout.

Then factor KYK \to Y as a cofibration followed by a weak equivalence KZYK \hookrightarrow Z \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} Y and push that factorization through the double diagram, to obtain

K cof Z W Y cof cof L cof L KZ W L KY W W L L KZ W X. \array{ K &\stackrel{\in cof}{\to}& Z &\stackrel{\in W}{\to}& Y \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in \cof}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow \\ L'' &\stackrel{\in cof}{\to}& L'' \coprod_{K} Z &\stackrel{\in W}{\to}& L'' \coprod_{K'} Y \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in W}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in W}} && \downarrow \\ L & \to& L \coprod_K Z &\stackrel{\in W}{\to}& X } \,.

Again by the behaviour of pushouts under pasting, every single square and composite rectangle in this diagram is a pushout. Using this, the cofibration and weak equivalence properties from before push through the diagram as indicated. This finally yields the desired weak equivalence

L KYX L'' \coprod_{K'} Y \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} X

by 2-out-of-3.

If we had allowed ourselved to assume in addition that KK itself is already cofibrant, then the above statement has a much simpler proof, which we list just for fun, too.

Proof of prop. 2 assuming that the domain of the cofibration is cofibrant

Let ABA \hookrightarrow B be a cofibration with AA cofibrant and let ACA \to C be any other morphism. Factor this morphism as ACCA \hookrightarrow C' \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} C by a cofibration followed by an acyclic fibration. This give a weak equivalence of pushout diagrams

C C A = A B = B. \array{ C' &\stackrel{\simeq}{\to}& C \\ \uparrow && \uparrow \\ A &\stackrel{=}{\to}& A \\ \downarrow && \downarrow \\ B &\stackrel{=}{\to}& B } \,.

In the diagram on the left all objects are cofibrant and one morphism is a cofibration, hence this is a cofibrant diagram and its ordinary colimit is the homotopy colimit. Using that pushout diagrams compose to pushout diagrams, that cofibrations are preserved under pushout and that in a left proper model category weak equivalences are preserved under pushout along cofibrations, we find a weak equiovalence hocolimB AChocolim \stackrel{\simeq}{\to} B \coprod_A C

A cof C Wfib C cof cof cof B hocolim W B AC. \array{ A &\stackrel{\in cof}{\to}& C' &\stackrel{\in W \cap fib}{\to}& C \\ \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} && \downarrow^{\mathrlap{\in cof}} \\ B &\to& hocolim &\stackrel{\in W}{\to}& B \coprod_A C } \,.

The proof for the second statement is the precise formal dual.

Proposition

A model category is right proper if and only if every fibration is a sharp map.

(Rezk 98)

Slice categories

For any model category MM, and any morphism f:ABf\colon A\to B, the adjunction

Σ f:M/AM/B:f * \Sigma_f : M/A \rightleftarrows M/B : f^*

is a Quillen adjunction. If this adjunction is a Quillen equivalence, then ff must be a weak equivalence. In general, the converse can be proven only if AA and BB are fibrant.

Theorem

The following are equivalent:

  1. MM is right proper.
  2. If ff is any weak equivalence in MM, then Σ ff *\Sigma_f \dashv f^* is a Quillen equivalence.

In other words, MM is right proper iff all slice categories have the “correct” Quillen equivalence type.

Since whether or not a Quillen adjunction is a Quillen equivalence depends only on the classes of weak equivalences, not the fibrations and cofibrations, it follows that being right proper is really a property of a homotopical category. In particular, if one model structure is right proper, then so is any other model structure on the same category with the same weak equivalences.

See this blog comment.

Local cartesian closure

Since most well-behaved model categories are equivalent to a model category in which all objects are fibrant — namely, the model category of algebraically fibrant objects — they are in particular equivalent to one which is right proper. Thus, right properness by itself is not a property of an (,1)(\infty,1)-category, only of a particular presentation of it via a model category.

However, if a Cisinski model category is right proper, then the (,1)(\infty,1)-category which it presents must be locally cartesian closed. Conversely, any locally cartesian closed (∞,1)-category has a presentation by a right proper Cisinski model category; see locally cartesian closed (∞,1)-category for the proof.

References

The usefulness of right properness for constructions of homotopy categories is discussed in

The general theory can be found in Chapter 13 of

  • Philip S. Hirschhorn, Model Categories and Their Localizations (AMS, pdf toc, pdf)

also in

See also

Revised on October 28, 2014 11:51:18 by Urs Schreiber (141.0.9.61)