This entry is about dualizing objects in closed (monoidal) categories in the sense of homological algebra and stable homotopy theory (e.g. dualizing modules). For a more general concept see at dualizing object.
abstract duality: opposite category,
concrete duality: dual object, dualizable object, fully dualizable object, dualizing object
Examples
between higher geometry/higher algebra
Langlands duality, geometric Langlands duality, quantum geometric Langlands duality
In QFT and String theory
A dualizing object in a closed category is an object such that the internal hom into it serves as an involutive duality operation on , or at least on a suitable full subcategory , i.e. it induces an equivalence of categories .
Let be a closed category, an object, and a full subcategory. We say that is a dualizing object on if the induced functor
is an equivalence of categories. Note that this includes the assumption that maps into itself, which is not automatic.
Note that we do not in general assume . In stable homotopy theory the subcategory in question is typically that of homotopy types with finite homotopy groups (e.g. for Anderson duality). Specifically in homological algebra one speaks also of dualizing modules. (See for instance (Heard-Stojanoska 14, def. 3.1 and Lurie, section 4.2).) Notably in a Grothendieck-Verdier context , of six operations the functor typically preserves dualizing objects in this sense, which is a crucial ingredient of Verdier duality.
If , we say that is a global dualizing object. A biclosed monoidal category with a global dualizing object is one definition of a star-autonomous category.
If is a closed symmetric monoidal category, then is adjoint to itself on the right, i.e. we have a natural isomorphism . Thus, if maps into itself, then its restriction to is an equivalence of categories if and only if the unit and counit of this adjunction are isomorphisms. But these unit and counit are both the βdouble-dualizationβ map
(the adjunct of the evaluation map , which in turn is the adjunct of the identity map ) for ; so is a dualizing object on if and only if preserves and these maps are isomorphisms for all .
If is a non-symmetric biclosed monoidal category, with two internal-homs and , then is adjoint on the right not to itself but to . A similar argument then shows that is dualizing if and only if and both map to itself, and both double-dualization maps
are isomorphisms.
A cartesian closed category that with a global dualizing object is necessarily just a preorder. This statement is often known as Joyalβs lemma, recalled for instance in Abramsky 09. It can be slightly strengthened as follows:
A cartesian closed category that is self-dual (carries an equivalence ) is necessarily a preorder (whose posetal reflection is then a Heyting algebra). If the self-duality comes from a dualizing object, then the Heyting algebra is a Boolean algebra.
For the first statement, let be terminal; then is an initial object , and similarly takes finite products to finite coproducts (coproducts are necessary for a Heyting algebra). So it remains to show is a preorder. Let be any two objects. The number of morphisms is the number of morphisms , which is the number of morphisms . But this is at most one since the initial object is strict (if there is any , then is a retract of , hence ; thus there is at most one morphism ).
The second statement is immediate: if is the dualizing object, then
so that is the negation and the hypothesis becomes the condition that double negation on the Heyting algebra is the identity, i.e., the Heyting algebra is a Boolean algebra.
In the stable (infinity,1)-category of spectra, the sphere spectrum (which induces Spanier-Whitehead duality on spectra which are dualizable objects with respect to the smash product of spectra) is not a dualizing object. However, the Anderson spectrum is a dualizing object on a suitable subcategory of finite spectra (Lurie, Example 4.3.9). The duality operation that it induces is Anderson duality.
For instance, the Anderson dual of KU is (complex conjugation-equivariantly) the 4-fold suspension spectrum (Heard-Stojanoska 14, theorem 8.2); and tmf is Anderson dual to its 21-fold suspension (Stojanoska 12)
In the category Sup of suplattices, the opposite of the poset of truth values is a global dualizing object (and hence is star-autonomous). The internal-hom is the suplattice of sup-preserving maps , hence is the suplattice of contravariant maps that take suprema in to infima in . But by the adjoint functor theorem for posets, any such map is representable by an element of ; thus . The double-dualization is therefore isomorphic to the identity .
The Chu construction is a (co)universal way of βmaking any object into a dualizing objectβ.
General discussion is in
Mitya Boryachenko, Vladimir Drinfeld, A duality formalism in the spirit of Grothendieck and Verdier (arXiv:1108.6020)
Jacob Lurie, section 4.2 of Representability Theorems
Reviews of the general concept and then discussion of Anderson duality is in
Vesna Stojanoska, Duality for Topological Modular Forms, Doc. Math. 17 (2012) 271-311 (arXiv:1105.3968)
Drew Heard, Vesna Stojanoska, K-theory, reality, and duality (arXiv:1401.2581)
Discussion in the context of the linear logic/quantum logic of quantum physics is in
Last revised on September 1, 2021 at 09:34:07. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.