homotopy theory, (∞,1)-category theory, homotopy type theory
flavors: stable, equivariant, rational, p-adic, proper, geometric, cohesive, directed…
models: topological, simplicial, localic, …
see also algebraic topology
Introductions
Definitions
Paths and cylinders
Homotopy groups
Basic facts
Theorems
…
…
In a locally -presentable (∞,1)-category, -filtered (∞,1)-colimits commute with -small (∞,1)-limits.
In particular, in a locally finitely presentable (∞,1)-category, filtered (∞,1)-colimits commute with finite (∞,1)-limits.
In an algebraic (∞,1)-category, i.e., one that is equivalent to the category of finite product-preserving functors from a small (∞,1)-category with finite products to the (∞,1)-category of spaces, sifted (∞,1)-colimits commute with finite (∞,1)-products.
From a MathOverflow answer:
Model categories provide a powerful framework for commuting (homotopy) limits and colimits, and, more generally, for commuting left adjoint functors and (homotopy) limits, as well as right adjoint functors and (homotopy) colimits. (In what follows, I omit the adjective “homotopy” before limits and colimits.)
In finitely presentable ∞-categories filtered colimits commute with finite limits and in finitely presentable ∞-categories with a set of compact projective generators sifted colimits commute with finite products. However, many other situations of interest are not covered by such statements. For instance, one might want to commute a sifted colimit past an infinite product, a pullback, or a cosifted limit (e.g., a cosimplicial totalization). One might also want to commute sifted colimits past finite products in ∞-categories that do not have a set of compact projective generators, e.g., the ∞-category of small ∞-categories.
In all such situations the relevant statement is false at least for some diagrams, so whatever criterion we devise must analyze the specific diagrams at question. This is precisely what model categories achieve.
For example, one might want to commute -indexed colimits (for some small diagram ) past some right adjoint functor . (For instance, one can take to be
the limit functor for -indexed diagrams, which will allows us to commute -indexed colimits past -indexed limits.)
We would like to devise a condition on a diagram that would guarantee that the canonical comparison map
is an equivalence in the ∞-category . This is achieved by the following creative procedure. First, consider the relative ∞-category (i.e., ∞-category equipped with a class of maps (weak equivalences) closed under composition) whose weak equivalences are created by the functor (i.e., a natural transformation of functors is a weak equivalence if its -colimit is an equivalence in the ∞-category ). The ∞-category is turned into a relative ∞-category in the same way. The functor
is a functor between ∞-categories that need not preserve weak equivalences.
Now comes the (potentially) creative part: equip the relative ∞-categories with model structures such that is a right Quillen functor. In many situations of interest this can be done immediately using existing tools.
Our criterion now says that if is a fibrant diagram, then the comparison map
is an equivalence in the ∞-category B, i.e., the colimit of over commutes with . Different choices of model structures give us different criteria.
For instance, one can take , (alias ∞-groupoids), (i.e., -indexed diagrams of spaces) and
the -indexed limit functor, where can be taken to be the pullback diagram or the infinite discrete category and the model structure can be taken to be the projective model structure. In this case we obtain a criterion for commuting -indexed colimits past -indexed limits. This recovers, for example, the traditional methods for computing homotopy pullbacks of simplicial sets (replace one of the legs by a fibration), infinite homotopy products of simplicial sets (fibrantly replace all terms), etc.
There are many variations on the above theme, for instance, one can consider weighted limits (in the sense of enriched category theory) and then derive the limit functor with respect to both the functor and the weight, which yields even more powerful computational tools etc.
Many classical results on model categories fit in the above framework. For instance, if is a simplicial model category, is a cofibrant object, and is a fibrant object, then the simplicial mapping space from to computes the mapping space in the ∞-localization of with respect to its weak equivalences. We can fit this in the above framework by taking
and observing that a cofibrant object has a cofibrant cosimplicial resolution .
Textbook accounts include Chapter 7 of Cisinski.
On conditions that base change via homotopy pullback commutes with realization (cf. π-Kan condition and this Prop.):
Aldridge Bousfield, Eric Friedlander, Homotopy theory of -spaces, spectra, and bisimplicial sets, Springer Lecture Notes in Math. 658 Springer (1978) 80-130 [pdf, pdf]
Jacob Lurie, Simplicial spaces, Lecture 7 of: Algebraic L-theory and Surgery (2011) [pdf]
Charles Rezk, When are homotopy colimits compatible with homotopy base change? (2014) [i-hate-the-pi-star-kan-condition.pdf, pdf]
Jacob Lurie, §A.5, esp. Def. A.5.2.1, Thms. A.5.3.1, A.5.4.1, A.5.6.1 in Spectral Algebraic Geometry (2018) [pdf]
For a treatment without ∞-categories, see also BEBP19, Def. 3.2, Ex. 3.10, Thm. 3.17 below.
An even larger class of maps of so-called weak Kan fibrations is studied in Section 3 of
The general theory of model (∞,1)-categories that allows one to commute homotopy colimits past homotopy limits is developed in a series of papers by Aaaron Mazel-Gee:
Aaron Mazel-Gee, Model ∞-categories I: some pleasant properties of the ∞-category of simplicial spaces [arXiv:1412.8411]
Aaron Mazel-Gee, Model ∞-categories II: Quillen adjunctions, New York Journal of Mathematics 27 (2021) 508-550. [arXiv:1510.04392, nyjm:27-21]
Aaron Mazel-Gee, Model ∞-categories III: the fundamental theorem, New York Journal of Mathematics 27 (2021) 551-599 [arXiv:1510.04777, nyjm:27-22]
and in
In particular, see Propositions 7.5.5, 7.7.4, 7.7.5.
Last revised on October 16, 2023 at 04:12:56. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.