analysis (differential/integral calculus, functional analysis, topology)
metric space, normed vector space
open ball, open subset, neighbourhood
convergence, limit of a sequence
compactness, sequential compactness
continuous metric space valued function on compact metric space is uniformly continuous
…
…
What came to be called Dedekind cuts (a notion due to Dedekind (1872)) is a way to make precise the idea that a real number is that which can be approximated (in the absolute value metric) by rational numbers.
Dedekind 1872 pointed out that a real number may be uniquely determined its order relationships with rational numbers. That is, the real number is determined by its lower set and its upper set :
Dedekind had found great success understanding the ‘ideal numbers’ of ring theory as certain sets, which are what we now understand as ideals. So he defined a ‘real number’ as a pair of sets of rational numbers, the lower and upper sets shown above (actually a slight variation). Such a pair of sets of rational numbers he called a ‘Schnitt’ (English ‘cut’), nowadays called a ‘Dedekind cut’.
Exactly which pairs of sets of rational numbers can appear this way? We will define a Dedekind cut to be any pair of sets of rational numbers satisfying these conditions:
Actually, this definition is redundant; any pair that satisfies (7&8) must also satisfy (3&4). However, we state (3&4) explicitly to simplify the description of the variations below.
If is a Dedekind cut, then we define to mean that and define to mean that .
This definition is due to Vickers15.
Let us define the family of upwards unbounded open intervals and lower unbounded open intervals . The set of Dedekind cuts is a frame generated by and such that
for all and ,
for all and ,
for all
for all
for all and ,
for all and ,
A Dedekind cut is an element of this frame.
There is a structural version of Dedekind cuts in structural set theory. A structural subset of the rational numbers is a set with an injection . We say that a rational number belongs to if there exists an element such that .
A structural Dedekind cut consists of two structural subsets and with injections and such that
The point of condition (7) is that we can estimate as closely as we like by choosing appropriate rational numbers.
This is entirely constructive. We have for some (by 1) and for some (by 2), so if we wish to estimate to within a positive rational number , then we simply let be and apply (7) to each of the finitely many () rational numbers with denominator that lie between and . This will eventually give us a numerator such that , so we have estimated within . Alternatively, to estimate to digits after a decimal point (with an uncertainty of in the last digit), apply (7) to each of the numbers between and that have digits after the decimal point. (We can never constructively determine the final digit with perfect certainty; for example, if we successively estimate as , no finite number of such estimates can ever ensure that won't come out to when we go one digit farther.)
Besides giving us a place to begin our estimation, (1&2) ensure that is finite. Condition (8) enforces the transitivity law ; (3&4) are likewise forms of transitivity. (5&6) ensure that, even if happens to be a rational number, we are using the sets and given in (1) instead of their closures (defined with instead of ).
We define to mean that there exists a rational number such that ; that is, some rational number belongs to both the upper set of and the lower set of . It is then straightforward to prove that is a linear order:
As usual with a linear order, we define to mean that is false. In particular, connectedness of corresponds to antisymmetry of .
We can also derive a Dedekind cut from any rational number by taking (1) to be the definition of as a Dedekind cut. Thus every rational number is interpreted as a real number. This is a strict inclusion of linear orders:
In this way, the Dedekind cuts form an extension of the linearly ordered set of rational numbers. More than that, this extension is Dedekind-complete, which basically means that you cannot extend further by taking Dedekind cuts of Dedekind cuts.
To be explicit, suppose that is a pair of sets of Dedekind cuts (rather than of rational numbers) that satisfies (1–8), using Dedekind cuts in place of rational numbers. Let be the union of the left halves of the cuts that appear in , and let be the union of the right halves of the cuts that appear in . Then one can prove that is a Dedekind cut (of rational numbers), and furthermore that and may be recovered from as in (1), again using Dedekind cuts in place of rational numbers.
We say that the Dedekind cuts form the Dedekind completion of the linear order .
Being a member of the lower (resp. the upper) set of a Dedekind cut is almost stable (under double negation): For any rational number it holds that iff there exists a rational number such that . “Only if” is by condition (5). “If” is by condition (7): We have or . In the first case we’re done; in the second case it follows that by (8), which is a contradiction to .
Equality of Dedekind cuts is stable (under double negation).
A Dedekind cut is, in full clarity, a bounded, open, rounded, located, two-sided Dedekind cut of rational numbers. But there are several simple variations on the definition above, many of which may be found in the literature.
The conditions (5&6) are not really necessary. If you leave them out, then the result that is a connected relation on Dedekind cuts fails; but instead we identify cuts and whenever . Then the linearly ordered set of real numbers becomes a quotient set of the set of cuts. In a similar vein, we can weaken (3,4,7) as follows:
Just as (3,4) follow from (7,8), so (3′,4′) follow from (7′,8). Again, is no longer connected, but we still get a linear order on a quotient set. The weakest axiom system that will give the correct linear order on the quotient is (1,2,7′,8). Incidentally, you can also recover the original definition using (3,4,7′) in place of (7).
To emphasise that one does require (5,6), one may speak of an open cut. To emphasise that one does require (3,4), one may speak of a rounded cut.
Note that we may elegantly (although requiring a fancier logic) combine (3,4,5,6) into two conditions as follows:
Another approach is to strengthen (7):
While (7″) alone does not imply (7), it does together with (8). Also note that, using (8), we can even change ‘or’ to ‘xor’ in (7″).
The cuts that satisfy (1–6, 7″, 8) are precisely the cuts that define irrational numbers. If we remove either (5) or (6), then the resulting axioms define one cut for each rational number as well. If we remove both (5) and (6), then we get two cuts for each rational number and must (as in the previous section) pass to a quotient; this was actually Dedekind's original 1872 system. These versions are not acceptable constructively (and we cannot even prove that they are closed under addition), but they work fine if you use excluded middle. (Actually, the somewhat weaker limited principle of omniscience seems to suffice.)
Suppose that we consider only and demand (1,3,5), the axioms that refer only to . Any such set of rational numbers is a lower cut. Similarly, a set that satisfies (2,4,6) is an upper cut. If we demand that the set or is a proper subset, then we have a bounded lower/upper cut. If we wish to emphasise that we are discussing a cut as defined above, with both and , we speak of a two-sided cut.
Assuming excluded middle, every bounded lower or upper cut generates a two-sided cut, by whichever of these rules is needed:
In addition, the unbounded lower cut represents , while the unbounded upper cut represents .
In constructive mathematics, one-sided cuts define a potentially more general notion of real number, called a lower real or upper real (with the same direction as the cut). Unlike the covering cuts in the previous section, these are actually of interest constructively. If we wish to emphasise or clarify that we are discussing a two-sided cut as in our original definition, rather than a one-sided cut which has been made two-sided through (2) (which may not satisfy (7) constructively), then we may speak of a located cut.
If we drop conditions (1&2), then the result is an extended cut; these represent extended real numbers. If we wish to emphasise or clarify that we are discussing a cut that satisfies (1,2), then we may speak of a bounded cut.
By excluded middle, every extended cut is either a Dedekind cut, , or . While the bounded cuts represent real numbers, the other two extended cuts represent .
If we drop (7) (but keep 3&4), then the result is an interval cut; these represent intervals of the form for , where is a lower real and is an upper real. If we use only (1–6), then we allow for back-to-front intervals where is no longer required. Even classically, we cannot represent back-to-front intervals as subsets of the real line, but it is still possible to compute with them.
Whereas a located Dedekind cut can be approximated as closely as we wish, an interval cut represents a number as we measure it in the real world, where we may not be technically able (or even theoretically able, as in quantum physics) to make a more precise measurement. A back-to-front interval indicates that we have made contradictory measurements, perhaps as a result of experimental error.
An article on interval arithmetic is probably the right place to talk about these systems (although there are many varieties of interval arithmetic).
In predicative mathematics, subsets are large and therefore are proper classes. Instead, in the manner of formal topology, they typically use pairs of functions representing the open subsets of to define -Dedekind cuts, where is a small -locale, or small -frame with an embedding into the large set of propositions for a universe . The definitions then become
For any two -frames and that embed into such that , if is the set of -Dedekind cuts of and is the -Dedekind cuts of , then .
Instead of starting with rational numbers, we could use any dense? subset of ; the result would be equivalent. For example, we could start with the dyadic numbers to show more explicitly how real numbers are represented by rational numbers written in binary notation. Alternatively, we could start with something larger than (or incomparable with) that is still a dense subset of (although you have to know what is to state this). For example, we could start with the real algebraic numbers or the computable numbers.
The basic theory also generalises immediately to any unbounded, dense linear order ; again, the result is equivalent as long as is a countably infinite set. The theory may be generalised further even to orders which may not be unbounded, dense, or even linear, but this requires modifications; see Dedekind completion for unbounded dense quasiorders or unbounded dense irreflexive comparisons or Sections 4.31–39 of HAF for even more generality.
The original article:
Richard Dedekind, Stetigkeit und irrationale Zahlen (1872) [Google Books, retyped: web]
Richard Dedekind (transl. by W. Beman), Continuity and irrational numbers, Chapter I in: Essays on the Theory of Numbers, Chicago (1901) [Project Gutenberg, pdf]
Review:
Discussion in locale-theory:
Discussion via abstract Stone duality:
Paul Taylor, Dedekind cuts (2007-2009?)
Andrej Bauer, Paul Taylor, The Dedekind reals in abstract Stone duality, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 19 4 (2009) 757-838 [doi:10.1017/S0960129509007695]
review in:
Discussion in synthetic topology:
Formalization in homotopy type theory:
Univalent Foundations Project, §11.2 Homotopy Type Theory – Univalent Foundations of Mathematics (2013) [web, pdf]
Auke B. Booij, Extensional constructive real analysis via locators, (abs:1805.06781)
Last revised on May 15, 2024 at 16:46:05. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.