Backround
Definition
Presentation over a site
Models
typical contexts
The definition of cohesive topos or category of cohesion aims to axiomatize properties of a topos that make it a gros topos of spaces inside of which geometry may take place. See also at motivation for cohesive toposes for a non-technical discussion.
The idea behind the term is that a geometric space is roughly something consisting of points or pieces that are held together by some cohesion - for instance by topology, by smooth structure, etc.
The canonical global section geometric morphism of a cohesive topos over Set may be thought of as sending a space to its underlying set of points . Here is with all cohesion forgotten (for instance with the topology or the smooth structure forgotten)
Conversely, the left adjoint and right adjoint of
send a set either to the discrete space with discrete cohesive structure (for instance with discrete topology) or to the codiscrete space with the codiscrete cohesive structure (for instance with codiscrete topology). (An instance of an adjoint cylinder/unity of opposites, a “category of being”).
Moreover, the idea is that cohesion makes points lump together to connected pieces . This is modeled by one more functor left adjoint to . In the context of 1-topos theory this sends a cohesive space to its connected components . More generally in an (n,1)-topos-theory context, sends a cohesive space to the -truncation of its geometric fundamental ∞-groupoid . See cohesive (∞,1)-topos.
In total this gives an adjoint quadruple
A cohesive topos is a topos whose terminal geometric morphism admits an extension to such a quadruple of adjoints, satisfying some further properties.
Notice that most objects in a cohesive topos are far from being just sets with extra structure: while the functor does produce the set of points underlying an object in the cohesive topos, it may happen that is very non-trivial but that nevertheless has very few points (possibly none, with the axioms so far). The subcategory of objects in that we may think of as point sets equipped with extra structure is the quasitopos of the concrete sheaves inside
It is the fact that is a local topos that allows to identify .
To ensure that there is a minimum of points, one can add further axioms. From the above adjunctions one gets a canonical natural morphism
from the points of to the set of connected pieces of . Demanding this to be an epimorphism is demanding that each piece has at least one point .
Moreover, one can demand that the cohesive pieces of product or power spaces are the products of the cohesive pieces of the factors. For powers of a single space, this is demanding that for all the following canonical map is an isomorphism:
For more general products, it would be a similar map . See the examples at cohesive site for concrete illustrations of these ideas.
A topos over some base topos , i.e. equipped with a geometric morphism
is cohesive if it is a
In detail this means that it has the following properties:
it is a locally connected topos: there exists a further left adjoint satisfying a suitable condition;
it is a connected topos: the functor preserves the terminal object, or equivalently is fully faithful;
it is strongly connected : preserves even all finite products;
it is a local topos: there exists a further right adjoint (this is sufficient for to be local, since we have already assumed it to be connected);
In summary is cohesive over if we have an quadruple of adjoint functor of the form
such that preserves finite products.
With being a full and faithful functor also is, as indicated (for instance by the discussion at adjoint triple).
Hence the definition of cohesion specifies two full subcategories, equivalent to each other, both reflective and one also coreflective.
Since a topos is a cartesian closed category it follows with the discussion here that both of these are exponential ideals. In fact the condition that the -inclusion is an exponential ideal is equivalent to the condition that preserves finite products.
To reflect the geometric interpretation of these axioms we will here and in related entries often name these functors as follows
The above adjoint quadruple canonically induces an adjoint triple of endofunctors on
Being idempotent monads/comonads on , these are modalities in the type theory (internal logic) of . As such we call them: the
In addition to the fundamental axioms of cohesion above, there are several further axioms that one may (or may not) want to impose in order to formalize the concept of cohesion.
equivalent over a Boolean base topos (Prop. below):
First we need some lemmas:
Let
be an adjoint triple, with a fully faithful functor. Denoting the adjunction units/counits as
adjunction | unit | counit |
---|---|---|
we have that the following composites of unit/counit components are equal:
We claim that the following diagram commutes:
This commutes, because:
the left square is the image under of naturality for on ;
the top square is naturality for on ;
the right square is naturality for on ;
the bottom commuting triangle is the image under of the zig-zag identity for on .
Moreover, notice that
the total bottom composite is the identity morphism , due to the zig-zag identity for ;
also the other two morphisms in the bottom triangle are isomorphisms, as shown, due to the idempoency of the -adjunction
Therefore the total composite from along the bottom part of the diagram equals the left hand side of (1), while the composite along the top part of the diagram clearly equals the right hand side of (1).
Consider an adjoint triple of the form
(for instance a cohesive topos over some base topos ).
Then for all the following two natural transformations, constructed from the adjunction units/counits and their inverse morphisms (using idempotency), are equal:
Moreover, the image of these morphisms under equals the following composite:
hence
Either of these morphisms we call the points-to-pieces transform.
The first statement is due to (Johnstone 11, Corollary 2.2).
The first statement follows directly from Lemma .
For the second statement, notice that the -adjunct of
is
where under the braces we uses the zig-zag identity.
(As a side remark, for later usage, we observe that the morphisms on the left in (5) are isomorphisms, as shown, by idempotency of the adjunctions.)
From this we obtain the following commuting diagram:
Here:
on the left we identified by applying the formula for -adjuncts to (5);
on the right we used the zig-zag identity for .
This proves the second statement.
Consider an adjoint triple
Then application of the functor on any morphism is equal both to the operations of
pre-composition with the -adjunction counit , followed by passing to the -adjunct;
post-composition with the -adjunction unit , followed by passing to the -adjunct:
For the first equality, consider the following naturality square for the adjunction hom-isomorphism (this Def.):
Chasing the identity morphism through this diagram, yields the claimed equality, as shown on the right. Here we use that the right adjunct of the identity morphism is the adjunction unit, as shown.
The second equality is fomally dual:
(pieces have points discrete objects are concrete)
Consider an adjoint quadruple of the form
(for instance a cohesive topos over some base topos ).
Then the following are equivalent:
discrete objects are concrete: For every object the discrete object is a concrete object, in that the sharp adjunction counit on is a monomorphism:
First observe the equivalence of the first two statements:
In one direction, assume that is an epimorphism. By (4) we have , but is a left adjoint and left adjoints preserve epimorphisms.
In the other direction, assume that is an epimorphism. By (2) and (5) we see that is re-obtained from this by applying and then composition with isomorphisms. But is again a left adjoint, and hence preserves epimorphisms, as does composition with isomorphisms.
By applying (2) again, we find in particular that pieces have points is also equivalent to being an epimorphism, for all . But this is equivalent to
being a monomorphism for all (by adjunction isomorphism and definition of epimorphism).
Now by Lemma , this is equivalent to
being a monomorphism, which is equivalent to being a monomorphism, hence to discrete objects are concrete.
In infinitesimal cohesion the points-to-pieces transform, def. , is required to be an equivalence.
In tangent cohesion the points-to-pieces transform, def. , is part of the canonical differential cohomology diagram.
This condition pieces have points may also be expressed as follows:
If is epi, then there is Aufhebung of the initial opposition, in that . Conversely if this holds and the base topos is a Boolean topos, then is epi.
This is Lawvere-Menni 15, lemma 4.1, 4.2.
We say pieces of powers are powers of pieces if for all and the natural morphism
is an isomorphism.
This morphism is the internal hom-adjunct of
where we use that by definition is full and faithful and then that preserves products).
These extra axioms are proposed in (Lawvere, Axiomatic cohesion).
For a cohesive topos, we say that its subobject classifier is connected if for the subobject classifier we have
This implies that for all also .
This appears as axiom 2 in (Lawvere, Categories of spaces).
There is some overlap between the structures and conditions appearing here and those considered in the context of Q-categories. See there for more details.
Another axiom to consider, also introduced by Lawvere (see at Aufhebung):
Say that a cohesive topos, def. , has Aufhebung of becoming if the sharp modality, def. , preserves the initial object
The Aufhebungs axiom def. is satisfied by all cohesive toposes with a cohesive site of definition, see at Aufhebung – Over cohesive sites.
In the Aufhebungs-axiom of def. , the extra exactness condition on the shape modality in def. , which says (in particular) that shape preserves the terminal object
finds a dual companion. It might make sense to consider the variant of the axioms of cohesion which say
there is an adjoint triple of idempotent (co-)monads ;
such that satisfies Aufhebung and satisfies co-Aufhebung.
We discuss properties of cohesive toposes. In
we comment on the interdependency of the collection of axioms on a cohesive topos. In
we discuss the induced notion of concrete objects that comes with every cohesive topos and in
the induced subcategory of objects with one point per piece.
Some of these phenomena have a natural
For a long list of further structures that are canonically present in a cohesive context see
For more structure available with a few more axioms see at
We record some relations between the various axioms characterizing cohesive toposes.
The axioms pieces have points and discrete objects are concrete are equivalent.
This is just a reformulation of the above proposition.
A sheaf topos that
is locally connected and connected;
satisfies pieces have points
also is
The statement of the first items appears as (Johnstone 11, prop. 1.6). The last item is then a consequence by definition.
For a sheaf topos the condition that it
is connected;
satisfies pieces have points
is equivalent to the condition that it
is hyperconnected;
is local.
This is (Johnstone 11, theorem 3.4).
The reflective subcategories of discrete objects and of codiscrete objects are both exponential ideals.
By the discussion at exponential ideal a reflective subcategories of a cartesian closed category is an exponential ideal precisely if the reflector preserves products. For the codiscrete objects the reflector preserves even all limits and for the discrete objects the reflector does so by assumption of strong connectedness.
A cohesive topos comes canonically with various subcategories, sub-quasi-toposes and subtoposes of interest. We discuss some of these.
For a cohesive topos, exhibits as a subtopos
By general properties of local toposes. See there.
The category is equivalent to the full subcategory of on those objects for which the unit
is an isomorphism.
By general properties of reflective subcategories. See there for details.
An object of the cohesive topos for which is a monomorphism we call a concrete object.
Write
for the full subcategory on concrete objects.
The functor is a faithful functor on morphisms precisely if is a concrete object.
In particular, the restriction makes the category of concrete objects a concrete category.
Observe that the composite morphism
is given (see adjunct) by postcomposition with the -unit
The condition that is a concrete object, hence that is a monomorphism is therefore equivalent (see there) to the condition that is a monomorphism, which is equivalent to being a faithful functor.
This means that in the formal sense discussed at stuff, structure, property we may regard as a category of sets equipped with cohesive structure .
The category is a quasitopos and a reflective subcategory of .
Let be a site of definition for with coverage , so that . Since is a subtopos, we have that is itself a category of sheaves on
which must correspond to another coverage : . Since we have this sequence of inclusions, we have an inclusion of coverages . We observe that the concrete objects in are precisely the -biseparated presheaves on . The claim then follows by standard facts of quasitoposes of biseparated presheaves.
Precisely if the cohesive topos satisfies the axiom discrete objects are concrete (saying that for all the canonical morphism is a monomorphism) then is a cohesive quasitopos in that we have a quadrupled of adjoint functors.
The axiom says precisely that the functor factors through . Also clearly factors through . Since is a full subcategory therefore the restriction of and to yields a quadruple of adjunctions as indicated.
Since by reflectivity limits in may be computed in , preserves finite products on .
Let be a cohesive topos with an epimorphism for all .
Let be the full subcategory on those objects for which is an isomorphism. Then
is a reflective subcategory and a coreflective subcategory
preserves coproducts.
the components of the reflector are epimorphisms.
This is theorem 2 in (Lawvere).
Since is a left adjoint it preserves colimits, as does of course . Therefore the collection of objects for which is an isomorphism is closed under colimits and hence has all colimits and the inclusion obviously preserves them.
To apply the adjoint functor theorem to deduce that therefore has a right adjoint it is sufficient to argue that is a locally presentable category. To see this, notice that is the inverter of , a certain 2-limit in Cat. Since the 2-category of accessible categories and accessible functors is closed under (non-strict) 2-limits in Cat, it follows that is accessible. Since we already know that it is also cocomplete it follows that it must be locally presentable.
Since by assumption preserves finite products and preserves all products, it follows that is also closed under finite products and in particular contains the terminal object . Since , being a topos, is an extensive category, it follows that preserves coproducts.
(…details…)
Using that is an epi, we find that is also closed under subobjects: if is a monomorphism then if in
the right vertical morphism is an iso, then so is the left vertical one.
(…details…).
It then also follows that is closed under arbitrary products.
(…details…)
This implies the existence of and the fact that is epi.
(…details…)
Every topos comes with its internal logic. From this internal perspective, the existence of extra external functors on – such as the and the on a cohesive topos – is manifested by the existence of extra internal logical operators. These may be understood as modalities equipping the internal logic with a structure of a modal logic.
For the case of local toposes, of which cohesive toposes are a special case, this internal modal interpretation of the extra external functor has been noticed in (AwodeyBirkedal, section 4.2). (Beware that in that reference the symbols “” and “#” are used precisely oppositely to their use here).
For a monomorphism in a cohesive topos, hence a proposition of type in the internal logic, we say that it is discretely true if the pullback in
is an isomorphism, where is the -unit on .
If a proposition is true over all discrete objects, then it is discretely true. More precisely, if for any discrete object we have that
is an isomorphism, then is discretely true.
Because if so, then
is an isomorphism and hence
is for all . Therefore in this case is an isomorphism and hence so is .
For the sheaf topos over CartSp (smooth spaces) and the inclusion of all closed -differential forms into all -forms, the proposition is “the -form is closed”. This is of course not true generally, but it is discretely true: over a discrete space every form is closed.
We discuss some cohesive toposes over sites with trivial coverage/topology, so that the category of sheaves is the category of presheaves
We discuss an example of a cohesive topos over a cohesive site that is about the simplest non-trivial example that there is: the Sierpinski topos. Simple as it is, it does serve to already illustrate some key points. The following site is in fact also an ∞-cohesive site and hence there is a corresponding example of a cohesive (∞,1)-topos: the Sierpinski (∞,1)-topos.
Consider the site given by the interval category
equipped with trivial topology. This evidently has an initial object (which makes it cosifted) and a terminal object .
The category of sheaves = presheaves on this is the arrow category
since a presheaf on is given by a morphism
in Set. We find
.
Trivial as this is, it does provide some insight into the interpretation of cohesiveness: by decomposing into its fibers, an object is an -indexed family of sets: . The “cohesive pieces” are the and there are -many of them. This is what computes, which clearly preserves products.
Moreover we find for :
;
(and evidently both these functors are full and faithful).
This matches the interpretation we just found: is the collection of elements of with no two of them lumped together by cohesion, while is all elements of lumped together.
The canonical morphism
is
Plugging in the above this is just
itself. Indeed, by the above interpretation, this sends each point to its cohesive component. It is not an epimorphism in general, because the fiber over an element may be empty: the cohesive component may have no points.
The above example is the simplest special case of a more general but still very simple class of examples.
First notice that for any small category, we have the left and right Kan extension of presheaves along the functor . By definition, this are the colimit and limit functors
If has a terminal object then
the colimit is given by evaluation on this object;
there is a further right adjoint
given by
The terminal object of is the initial object of the opposite category and therefore the limit over any functor is given by evaluation on this object
To see that we have a pair of adjoint functors we check the natural hom-set equivalence by computing
Here the first step is the expression of natural transformations by end-calculus, the second uses the fact that Set is a cartesian closed category, the third uses that any hom-functor sends coends in the first argument to ends, and the last one uses the co-Yoneda lemma.
The formal dual of this statement is the following.
If has an initial object then
the limit is given by evaluation on this object;
there is a further left adjoint ,
so that preserves all small limits and in particular all finite products.
In summary we have
If has both an initial object as well as a terminal object then there is a quadruple of adjoint functors
where
is given by evaluation on ;
is given by evaluation of and preserves products.
The above interpretation of the cohesiveness encoded by still applies to the general case: a general object is, by restriction to the unique morphism in a set-indexed family of sets
and picks out the total set of points, while picks of the indexing set (“of cohesive components”). The extra information for general with initial and terminal object is that for every object these cohesive lumps of points are refined to a hierarchy of lumps and lumps-of-lumps
The category of reflexive directed graphs is a cohesive topos.
The category of just directed graphs, not necessarily reflexive, is not a cohesive topos.
This example was considered in (Lawvere, Categories of spaces) as a simple test case for two very similar toposes, one of which is cohesive, the other not.
We spell out some details on the cohesive topos of reflexive directed graphs.
A presheaf on this is a reflexive directed graph : the set is the set of all edges and vertices regarded as identity edges, the projection
sends each edge to its source and the projection
sends each edge to its target. The identities
and
express the fact that source and target are identity edges.
Equivalently, this is a presheaf on the full subcategory of the simplex category on the objects and
In fact this is the Cauchy completion of , obtained by splitting the idempotents.
In summary this shows that
We have an equivalence of categories
To see that this presheaf topos is cohesive, notice that the terminal geometric morphism
is the reflexive directed graph with set of vertices and no non-identity morphisms and is the set of vertices = identity edges.
The extra left adjoint sends a graph to its set of connected components, the coequalizer of the source and target maps
Since this is a reflexive coequalizer (by the existence of the unit map ) it does preserve products (as discussed there). This is the property that fails for the topos of all directed graphs: a general coequalizer does not preserve products.
And sends a set to the reflexive graph with vertices and one edge for every ordered pair of vertices (the indiscrete or chaotic graph).
The canonical morphism sends each vertex to its connected component. Evidently this is epi, hence in cohesive pieces have points .
Let be the simplex category, regarded as a site with the trivial coverage.
The corresponding sheaf topos is the presheaf topos sSet of simplicial sets.
Notice that reflexive directed graphs are equivalently skeleta of simplicial sets.
The category sSet of simplicial sets is a cohesive topos in which cohesive pieces have points .
We have for
;
, the set of connected components.
And for :
the constant simplicial set on ;
the simplicial set which in degree has the set of -tuples of elements of .
If are Kan complexes, then is the set of simplicial homotopy-classes of maps . We can therefore write the homotopy category of Kan complexes as
We discuss here presentations of cohesive toposes as categories of sheaves over sites equipped with suitable extra properties: “cohesive sites” (Def. ) below. The definition is readily motivated from the following basic Example , which constitutes the special case of cohesive sites with trivial coverage:
(adjoint quadruple of presheaves over site with terminal objects)
Let be a small category with finite products (hence with a terminal object and for any two objects their Cartesian product ).
Then there is an adjoint quadruple of functors between the category of presheaves over (this def.), and the category of sets (this Def.)
such that:
the functor sends a presheaf to its set of global sections, which here is its value on the terminal object:
and are full and faithful functors (this def.).
preserves finite products:
for , we have a natural bijection
Hence the category of presheaves over a small category with finite products is a cohesive topos (Def. ).
The existence of the terminal object in means equivalently, (by this Example) that there is an adjoint pair of functors between and the terminal category (this def.):
whose right adjoint takes the unique object of the terminal category to that terminal object.
From this it follows (by this example) that Kan extension produces an adjoint quadruple of functors between the category of presheaves and , as shown, where
is the operation of pre-composition with the terminal object inclusion
is the left Kan extension along the inclusion of the terminal object.
The former is manifestly the operation of evaluating on the terminal object. Moreover, since the terminal object inclusion is manifestly a fully faithful functor (this def.), it follows that also its left Kan extension is fully faithful (this prop.). This implies that also is fully faithful, by this prop..
Equivalently, is the constant diagram-assigning functor. By uniqueness of adjoints (this prop.) implies that is the functor that sends a presheaf, regarded as a functor , to its colimit
The fact that this indeed preserves products follows from the assumption that has finite products, since categories with finite products are cosifted (this prop.)
Example suggests to ask for coverages on categories with finite products which are such that the adjoint quadruple (7) on the category of presheaves (co-)restricts to the corresponding category of sheaves. The following Definition states a sufficient condition for this to be the case:
We call a site (this def.) cohesive if the following conditions are satisfied:
The category has finite products (as in Example ).
For every covering family in the given coverage on the induced Cech groupoid (this def.) satisfies the following two conditions:
the set of connected components of the groupoid obtained as the colimit over the Cech groupoid is the singleton:
the set of connected components of the groupoid obtained as the limit of the Cech groupoid is equivalent to the set of points of , regarded as a groupoid:
This definition is designed to make the following true:
(category of sheaves on a cohesive site is a cohesive topos)
Let be a cohesive site (Def. ). Then the adjoint quadruple on the category of presheaves over , from Example (given that a cohesive site by definition has finite products) (co-)restricts from the category of presheaves over , to the category of sheaves (this def.) and hence exhibits as a cohesive topos (Def. ):
With Example it only remains to be shown that for each set the presheaves and are indeed sheaves.
By the formulaton of the sheaf condition via the Cech groupoid (this prop), and using the adjunction hom-isomorphisms (here) this is readily seen to be equivalent to the two further conditions on a cohesive site (Def. ):
Let be a covering family.
The sheaf condition (in this form) for says that
is an isomorphism of groupoids, which by adjunction and using (9) means equivalently that
is an isomorphism of groupoids, where we used that colimits of representables are singletons (this Lemma) to replace .
But now in this internal hom of groupoids, the set is really a groupoid in the image of the reflective embedding of sets into groupoids, whose left adjoint is the connected components-functor (this example). Hence by another adjunction isomoprhism this is equivalent to
being an isomorphism (a bijection of sets, now). This is true for all precisely if (by the Yoneda lemma, if you wish) the morphism
is already an isomorphism (here: bijection) itself.
Similarly, the sheaf condition (in this form) for says that
is an isomorphism, and hence by adjunction and using (8), this is equivalent to
being an isomorphism. This holds for all if (by the Yoneda lemma, if you wish)
is an isomorphism.
(smooth sets form a cohesive topos)
The category of smooth sets (this Def.) is a cohesive topos (Def. )
First of all (by this Prop) smooth sets indeed form a sheaf topos, over the site CartSp of Cartesian spaces with smooth functions between them, and equipped with the coverage of differentiably-good open covers (this def.)
Hence, by Prop. , it is now sufficient to see that CartSp is a cohesive site (Def. ).
It clearly has finite products: The terminal object is the point, given by the 0-dimensional Cartesian space
and the Cartesian product of two Cartesian spaces is the Cartesian space whose dimension is the sum of the two separate dimensions:
This establishes the first clause in Def. .
For the second clause, consider a differentiably-good open cover (this def.). This being a good cover implies that its Cech groupoid is, as an internal groupoid (via this remark), of the form
where we used the defining property of good open covers to identify .
The colimit of (12), regarded just as a presheaf of reflexive directed graphs (hence ignoring composition for the moment), is readily seen to be the graph of the colimit of the components (the universal property follows immediately from that of the component colimits):
Here we first used that colimits commute with colimits, hence in particular with coproducts (this prop.) and then that the colimit of a representable presheaf is the singleton set (this Lemma).
This colimiting graph carries a unique composition structure making it a groupoid, since there is at most one morphism between any two objects, and every object carries a morphism from itself to itself. This implies that this groupoid is actually the colimiting groupoid of the Cech groupoid: hence the groupoid obtained from replacing each representable summand in the Cech groupoid by a point.
Precisely this operation on Cech groupoids of good open covers of topological spaces is what Borsuk's nerve theorem is about, a classical result in topology/homotopy theory. This theorem implies directly that the set of connected components of the groupoid (14) is in bijection with the set of connected components of the Cartesian space , regarded as a topological space. But this is evidently a connected topological space, which finally shows that, indeed
The second item of the second clause in Def. follows similarly, but more easily: The limit of the Cech groupoid is readily seen to be, as before, the unique groupoid structure on the limiting underlying graph of presheaves. Since has a terminal object , which is hence an initial object in the opposite category , limits over yield simply the evaluation on that object:
Here we used that colimits (here coproducts) of presheaves are computed objectwise, and then the definition of the Yoneda embedding .
But the equivalence relation induced by this graph on its set of objects precisely identifies pairs of points, one in the other in , that are actually the same point of the being covered. Hence the set of equivalence classes is the set of points of , which is just what remained to be shown:
The quasitopos of concrete objects in the cohesive topos of smooth sets (Example ) is the category of diffeological spaces.
A sheaf on is a separated presheaf with respect to the further localization given by precisely if the canonical morphism (the unit of )
is a monomorphism. Monomorphisms of sheaves are tested objectwise, so that this is equivalent to
being a monomorphism for all (where in the first step we used the Yoneda lemma). By the adjunction relation this is equivalently
This being a monomorphism is precisely the condition on being a concrete sheaf on that singles out diffeological spaces among all sheaves on .
The site ThCartSp with the standard open cover coverage is a cohesive site and even an (∞,1)-cohesive site.
The corresponding cohesive topos is the Cahiers topos . This is a smooth topos that models the axioms of synthetic differential geometry.
(…)
Let be a cohesive topos and an object.
A necessary conditions that the over topos is a connected topos is that
Sufficient condition for to be a local topos is that
See at differential cohesion. Examples include the Cahiers topos
Consider a full subcategory inclusion
which has a left adjoint and a right adjoint that coincide with each other
In (Lawvere 07, def. 1) this situation is said to exhibit as a quality type over .
It follows that there is an infinite sequence of adjoints, in particular that there is right adjoint to , which by the discussion at adjoint triple is also a full and faithful functor, and that preserves finite products (in fact all limits).
So the above adjoints makes be a cohesive topos over the base topos with the special property that . In words this says that in every cohesive neighbourhood contains precisely one point. This is a characteristic of infinitesimally thickened points.
See at infinitesimal cohesion for more on this.
Counter-Example
Let be a non-trivial finite group of cardinality . Write for its delooping groupoid. The presheaf topos
is the category of permutation representations of . It comes with a triple of adjoint functors
The colimit over a representation is quotient set . So we have
but
where denotes the fundamental representation of on itself. Therefore does not preserve products in this case.
cohesive topos / cohesive (∞,1)-topos
and
The axioms for a cohesive topos originate around
where however the term “cohesive topos” was not yet used.
This appears maybe first in
The term “cohesion” and parts of its later axiomatization (p. 245) appears thoughout section C.1 of
Under the name categories of cohesion a formal axiomatization is given in
(This does demand the conditions that “cohesive pieces have points” and that “pieces of powers are powers of pieces” as part of the definition of “category of cohesion”.)
This builds on a series of precursors of attempts to identify axiomatics for gros toposes.
In
the term category of Being is used for a notion resembling that of a cohesive topos (with an adjoint quadruple but not considering pieces have points or discrete objects are concrete). Behaviour of objects with respect to the extra left adjoined is interpreted in terms of properties of Becoming. The terminology here is probably inspired from
and specifically the term “cohesion” probably from
In
a proposal for a general axiomatization of homotopy/homology-like “extensive quantities” and cohomology-like “intensive quantities”) as covariant and contravariant functors out of a distributive category are considered.
The left and right adjoint to the global section functor as a means to identify discrete spaces and codiscrete space is mentioned
on page 14.
The precise term cohesive topos apparently first appeared publically in the lecture
Notes for these lectures are in this pdf, made available on Bob Walters‘s Como Category Theory Archive.
The notion of “cohesion” was explored earlier in
where (on p. 9) it is suggested that “almost any” extensive category may be called a “species of cohesion”.
An analysis of the interdependency of the axioms on a cohesive topos is in
Discussion of “sufficient cohesion” is in
Matías Menni, Continuous Cohesion over sets, Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 29, 2014, No. 20, pp 542-568. (TAC, pdf)
Matías Menni, Sufficient Cohesion over Atomic Toposes , Cah. Top.Géom. Diff. Cat. LV (2014) (preprint)
Discussion of relation to double negation topology is in
And further relations of cohesion to Birkhoff's theorem in universal algebra is given in
A good deal of the structure of cohesive toposes is also considered in
under the name Q-categories.
The internal logic of local toposes is discussed in
Notation and terminology above, and generalization to differential cohesion etc., follows:
Exposition:
Last revised on December 14, 2022 at 09:10:52. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.