The notion of geometric theory has many different incarnations. A few are:
A geometric theory is a (possibly infinitary) first order theory whose models are preserved and reflected by geometric morphisms.
A geometric theory is a (possibly infinitary) first order theory whose axioms can be written as sequents in context of formulae constructed from the connectives (truth), (finite conjunction), (falsity), (possibly infinitary disjunction), and (existential quantification), as well as (equality).
A geometric theory is a syntactic description of a Grothendieck topos.
The equivalence of these statements involves some serious proofs, including Giraud's theorem characterizing Grothendieck topoi.
In logical terms, a geometric theory fits into a hierarchy of theories that can be interpreted in the internal logic of a hierarchy of types of categories. Since predicates in the internal logic are represented by subobjects, in order to interpret any connective or quantifier in the internal logic, one needs a corresponding operation on subobjects to exist in the category in question, and be well-behaved. For instance:
Since and are represented by intersections and identities (top elements), and is represented by equalizer, these can be interpreted in any lex category. Theories involving only these are examples of cartesian theories.
Since is represented by the image of a subobject, it can be interpreted in any regular category. Theories involving only , , and are regular theories.
Since and are represented by union and bottom elements, these can be interpreted in any coherent category. Theories which add these to regular logic are called coherent theories.
Finally, theories which also involve infinitary , which is again represented by an infinitary union, can be interpreted in infinitary coherent categories, aka geometric categories. These are geometric theories.
Note that the axioms of one of these theories are actually of the form
where and are formulas involving only the specified connectives and quantifiers, means entailment, and is a context. Such an axiom can also be written as
so that although and are not strictly part of any of the above logics, they can be applied “once at top level.” In an axiom of this form for geometric logic, the formulas and which must be built out of , , , , and are sometimes called positive or geometric formulas.
The interpretation of arbitrary uses of and requires a Heyting category. In fact, by the adjoint functor theorem for posets, any geometric category which is well-powered is automatically a Heyting category, but geometric functors are not necessarily Heyting functors. Likewise, a well-powered geometric category automatically has arbitrary intersections of subobjects as well, so we can interpret infinitary in its internal logic, but again these are not preserved by geometric functors.
By the usual syntactic constructions (see internal logic and context), any geometric theory generates a “free geometric category containing a model of that theory,” also known as its syntactic category . This syntactic category has the universal property that for any other geometric category , geometric functors are equivalent to -models in .
Let be a signature, then the set of all geometric sequents over as well as the empty set are geometric theories called the inconsistent theory resp. the empty theory over . The former admits a more concise axiomatisation as . The most basic examples occur when the signature is empty: is classified by the initial topos and is classified by the terminal topos (see at classifying topos for details).
The empty signature occurring in the preceding example is an extreme case of a propositional signature i.e. one lacking sort symbols. These can at most contain 0-ary relation symbols since function symbols and higher order relation symbols require sorts. Whence theories over such signatures can at most contain sequents in the empty context between formulas consisting of quantifier-free nestings of 0-ary relation symbols and and are therefor called propositional theories - in other words: geometric logic boils down to propositional logic. Propositional theories are classified by localic toposes (see there for further information).
Any finitary algebraic theory is, in particular, a cartesian theory, and hence geometric. This includes monoids, groups, abelian groups, rings, commutative rings, etc.
The theory of categories with models the (strict) categories is not finitary-algebraic, but it is cartesian, and hence geometric; this generalises to (finitary) essentially algebraic theories.
The theory of torsion-free abelian groups is also cartesian, being obtained from the theory of abelian groups by the addition of the sequents for all .
The theory of local rings is a coherent theory, being obtained from the theory of commutative rings by adding the sequent , for nontriviality, and
saying that if is invertible, then either or is so.
The theory of fields is also coherent, being obtained from the theory of commutative rings by adding and also
asserting that every element is either zero or invertible. In the constructive logic that holds internal to the categories in question, this is the notion of a “discrete field;” other classically equivalent axiomatizations (called “Heyting fields” or “residue fields” – see field) are not coherent.
The theory of torsion abelian groups is geometric but not coherent; it can be obtained from the theory of abelian groups by adding the sequent
asserting that for each , either or or or …. Similarly, the theory of fields of finite characteristic is geometric but not coherent.
The theory of the standard successor algebra is geometric. Its signature has one sort symbol , one function symbol and one constant . The theory axiomaticizes natural number objects by taking advantage of the availability of infinitary disjunctions in geometric logic in order to assert in the third axiom that every natural number is standard i.e. either 0 or obtained from 0 by (repeated) application of the successor function:
The classifying topos is . But due to the trivial subtopos lattice, theories classified by Set admit no consistent quotient theories; thus the geometric theory of natural numbers is complete! Furthermore, since is the terminal topos, classifying also the empty theory, one sees that the object/type of natural numbers “comes for free” in geometric logic. This observation underlies the ideas for a geometric type theory (for more on this see there or the article by Vickers).
The theory of a real number is geometric. This is a propositional theory, having no sorts, and having one relation symbol “” for each pair of rational numbers . Its axioms are:
The classifying topos of this theory is the topos of sheaves on the real numbers.
The theory of flat diagrams1 over a small category is geometric. For each object of there is a sort , and for each morphism a function symbol . The axioms are -
( and )
()
This theory is classified by the topos of presheaves over .
It is commonly more useful to consider the theory of flat presheaves over , in other words the flat diagrams over . (Elephant calls these torsors over , generalizing the established terminology for groups.) This is because the representable presheaves are flat, and so Yoneda’s lemma transforms objects of covariantly into models of the theory. In fact, the models of the theory are the filtered colimits of representables. For example, a finitary algebraic theory is classified by the topos of covariant functors from the category of finitely presented algebras to .
If is a small site, by adding a geometric axiom schema to express J-continuity to the theory of flat diagrams, one obtains the theory of J-continuous flat diagrams, which is classified by . This answers in principle the question, given a site representation what geometric theory is classified by a Grothendieck topos? Of course, in practice one would like to have more concise and less unwieldy axiomatizations.
For any geometric theory there exists a geometric theory called the theory of -model homomorphisms whose models in a Grothendieck topos are precisely the homomorphisms between -models in :
A geometric theory whose classifying topos is a presheaf topos is called a theory of presheaf type.
Categories of each “logical” type can also be “completed” with respect to a suitable “exactness” property, without changing their internal logic. Any regular category has an completion into an exact category (see regular and exact completion), any coherent category has a completion into a pretopos, and any geometric category has a completion into an infinitary pretopos.
However, Giraud's theorem says that an infinitary pretopos having a generating set is precisely a Grothendieck topos. Moreover, a functor between Grothendieck topoi is geometric (preserves all the structure of a geometric category) iff it preserves finite limits and small colimits. By the adjoint functor theorem, this implies that it is the inverse image part of a geometric morphism, i.e. an adjunction in which (the “inverse image”) preserves finite limits.
Thus:
Grothendieck topoi and inverse-image functors are in some sense the “natural home” for models of geometric theories.
Note, though, that geometric morphisms are generally considered as pointing in the direction of the direct image , which is the opposite direction to the geometric functor . (This is because when and are the toposes of sheaves on sober topological spaces (or locales) and respectively, then continuous maps correspond precisely to geometric morphisms .) Also, of course any Grothendieck topos is an elementary topos (at least, as long as one works in foundations for which Set is an elementary topos), and hence its internal logic also includes “higher-order” constructions such as function-objects and power-objects. However, these are not preserved by geometric functors, so they (like and ) are not part of geometric logic. (They are, however, preserved by logical functors, a different sort of morphism between topoi.)
In particular, we can apply the “exact completion” operation to the syntactic category of a geometric theory to obtain an infinitary pretopos . As long as the theory was itself small, will have a generating set, and therefore will be a Grothendieck topos. The universal property of the syntactic category, combined with that of the exact completion, implies that for any Grothendieck topos , geometric morphisms are equivalent to -models in . This topos is called the classifying topos of .
In the other direction, if is any small site, we can write down a “geometric theory of cover-preserving flat functors .” By Diaconescu's theorem classifying geometric morphisms into sheaf topoi, it follows that is a classifying topos for this theory. Therefore, not only does every geometric theory have a classifying topos, every Grothendieck topos is the classifying topos of some theory. Very different-looking theories can have equivalent classifying topoi; this of course implies that they have all the same categories of models in all Grothendieck topoi up to equivalence (hence a Grothendieck topos is the “extensional categorical essence” of a geometric theory). We say that two geometric theories with equivalent classifying topoi are Morita equivalent.
We can approach the same idea by starting instead from the notions of Grothendieck topos and geometric morphism. The following approach is described in B4.2 of the Elephant.
Suppose we consider what sorts of “theories” we can define in terms of Grothendieck topoi, that are preserved by inverse image functors. Any such theory should certainly define a 2-functor , where is the 2-category of Grothendieck topoi and geometric morphisms, so for the moment let’s call any such a “theory”. The image of a functor is supposed to be “the category of -models,” and a classifying topos for such a 2-functor will be just a representing object for it.
Of course, this notion of theory is far too general; we only want to consider theories that are constructed in some reasonable way. One theory that should certainly be geometric is the theory of objects, . This 2-functor sends a topos to itself, considered as a mere category, and an inverse image functor to itself, considered as a mere functor. The theory can be shown to have a classifying topos, the object classifier . Similarly, we have a theory of -tuples of objects that should be geometric.
How can we construct more theories that ought to be geometric? We should start from some finite collection of objects (i.e. a model of ), “construct some new objects and morphisms,” and then “impose some axioms on them.” For any theory , let’s call a transformation a geometric construct. This is supposed to be “an object constructed out of the axioms of in a natural way.” More precisely, to every -model in a topos it assigns an object of , in a way that varies naturally with morphisms of -models and inverse image functors.
Now define a simple functional extension of to be the inserter of a pair of geometric constructs . A model of such a theory will consist of a model of , together with an additional morphism between two objects constructed out of the given -model. By iteratively applying such constructions, we can add in any number of new morphisms between “constructed objects.”
Finally, define a simple geometric quotient of to be the inverter of a modification between a pair of geometric constructs . That is, we require that a certain naturally defined morphism between objects constructed out of -models must be an isomorphism. (Applying equalizers, we see that this also includes the ability to set morphisms equal, i.e. to construct equifiers.)
From this point of view, a geometric theory is a theory obtained from some by a finite sequence of simple functional extensions and simple geometric quotients. Of course, once we know that each has a classifying topos, it follows immediately that any geometric theory has a classifying topos, since has inserters and inverters.
The following definition is sort of a “halfway house” between logic and geometry. Start with a first-order signature (this is the logical part). Then we have a 2-functor sending a topos to the category of -structures in . A geometric theory over is defined to consist of the following.
The equivalence of this definition with the others can be found in
It is not sufficient, in the third condition, to restrict to the case when is a singleton, but it is sufficient to consider the case when is a singleton together with all families of coproduct injections .
By framing this notion in the internal language of a topos we can talk of geometric theories over , with models in bounded -toposes (the relative version of “Grothendieck topos”). As a simple example, if we have a sheaf of rings on a topological space we can describe left -modules as models of a geometric theory over , the topos of sheaves on , and this notion is definable in -toposes.
Similarly to the -based case, given a geometric theory over a topos , we can form the -topos that classifies , for which the category of -models in a bounded -topos is naturally equivalent to the category of morphisms of -toposes . In other words
Since the classifying topos encodes the “extensional essence” of a geometric theory, it makes sense to define a map of theories to be a morphism of -toposes . Equivalently, of course, this is a -model in . Composition with induces a functor, forget along , from -models to -models in any -topos.
Define the gros category? of -models to have as objects pairs where is an -topos and is a -model in . A map is given by a morphism of -toposes and a homomorphism of -models in . The composition of maps should be evident. A map of geometric theories over induces a forgetful functor which leaves unchanged the -topos of residence, which has a left adjoint which may change the topos. For if is a -model in , pulling back along yields a -model, not in but in the pullback. This is a consequence of general facts about finite 2-limits of the 2-category of bounded -toposes.
The 2-categorical version of is useful in generalization of the spectrum construction: See at Cole's theory of spectrum.
Review:
Textbook accounts:
Peter Johnstone, sections B4.2, D1.1 of Sketches of an Elephant
Michael Makkai, Gonzalo E. Reyes, First Order Categorical Logic , LNM 611, Springer Berlin 1977. (draft)
A textbook account of (finitary) geometric logic can be found in
A systematic introduction to topos theory and geometric logic can be found in the following draft by O. Caramello:
which has become a chapter of the following monograph exploring first-order model theory in the context of Grothendieck toposes:
For additional background on (finitary) geometric formulas consider:
Karel Stokkermans, Bill Lawvere, and Steve Vickers: Catlist discussion March 1999 . (link)
H.J. Keisler: Theory of models with generalized atomic formulas , JSL 25 (1960), pp.1-26.
Discussion in the context of computer science is in
Discussion with an eye towards geometric type theory is in
Discussion with an eye towards quantum physics:
Stone duality for geometric theories is discussed in:
A nice short exposition together with an unorthodox proposal to expand geometric logic with fix point operators can be found here:
This is also sometimes called the theory of flat functors on . ↩
Last revised on May 3, 2024 at 10:06:45. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.