nLab
lens (in computer science)

Contents

Contents

Idea

In computer science, originally in database theory, a concept called lenses is used to formally capture situations where some structure is converted to a different form – a view – in such a way that changes made to the view can be reflected as updates to the original structure. The same construction has been devised on numerous occasions (Hedges).

An insightful explanation and critique of the concept of “lenses” is offered in Spivak 19 (exposition in Spivak ACT19), where it is argued that the notion may and should be regarded as a small fragment (namely that of trivial display maps) of the general notion of (categorical semantics for) dependent types, such as discussed at hyperdoctrine and related entries.

This perspective, however, it’s not the end of the story. Lenses were born as abstract gadgetry to implement bidirectional (i.e. read/write) accessors for data structures, and this idea can be extended in numerous directions. Notably, optics are a better generalisation of lenses for these uses and indeed emerged first in the functional programming literature.

In this sense, lenses are but the elementary manifestation of two more interesting mathematical frameworks: fibrations and optics (thus Tambara modules?).

More recently, lenses and optics (including both the dependent and non-dependent versions) have been adopted in the context of categorical systems theory, since they represent a bidirectional stateful computation remindful of the way some systems expose and update their internal state. For instance, see first chapter of (Myers and Spivak) or (Hedges 21).

Definition

Let (C,1,×)(\mathbf{C}, 1, \times) be a category with finite products.

Definition

Let S,VS,V be objects of C\mathbf C. A lens LL, with source SS and view VV, is a pair of arrows get:SV\mathrm{get} : S \to V and put:V×SS\mathrm{put} : V \times S \to S, often taken to satisfy the following equations, or lens laws:

  1. (PutGet) the get of a put is the projection: getput=π 0\mathrm{get} \mathrm{put} = \pi_0.
  2. (GetPut) the put for a trivially updated state is trivial: putget,1 S=1 S\mathrm{put} \langle \mathrm{get}, 1_S \rangle = 1_S.
  3. (PutPut) composing puts does not depend on the first view update: put(1 V×put)=putπ 0,2\mathrm{put}(1_V \times \mathrm{put}) = \mathrm{put} \pi_{0,2}.

Remark

The two morphisms comprising a lens can also be called ‘view’ and ‘update’. More generally, they are referred to as the ‘forward’ and ‘backward’ parts of the lens.

Remark

Sometimes a lens satisfying all three laws is said to be lawful. Sometimes it is said that a well-behaved lens satisfies (1) and (2) and a very well-behaved lens satisfies also (3).

The category of lenses

Lenses (regardless of their lawfulness) organize in a category Lens(C)\mathrm{Lens}(\mathbf C) whose objects are the same as C\mathbf C and whose morphisms XYX \to Y are lenses with states XX and views YY. The identity lens is given by (1 X,π 1):XX(1_X, \pi_1) :X \to X. Composition of (get 1,put 1):XY(\mathrm{get}_1, \mathrm{put}_{1}):X \to Y and (get 2,put 2):YZ(\mathrm{get}_2, \mathrm{put}_{2}):Y \to Z is given by:

get 12=get 1get 2 \mathrm{get}_{12} = \mathrm{get}_1 \circ \mathrm{get}_2
put 12=put 1put 21 Z,get 1,1 X1 Z,Δ X \mathrm{put}_{12} = \mathrm{put}_1 \circ \langle \mathrm{put}_2 \circ \langle 1_Z, \mathrm{get}_1\rangle, 1_X \rangle \circ \langle 1_Z, \Delta_X \rangle

The put 12\mathrm{put}_{12} morphism is probably easier to describe using generalized elements:

put 12:(z,x)put 1(put 2(z,get 1(x)),x) \mathrm{put}_{12} : (z,x) \mapsto \mathrm{put}_1(\mathrm{put}_2(z, \mathrm{get}_1(x)), x)

Remark

Crucially, associativity of this composition relies on naturality of the diagonals, which is a given in cartesian categories but not in more general monoidal categories. Optics are a sweeping generalization of lenses which overcomes this obstacle.

Moreover, the cartesian product of C\mathbf C endows Lens(C)\mathrm{Lens}(\mathbf{C}) of a monoidal product.

Properties

Proposition

Lenses are algebras for a monad generated by the adjunction:

Proof

See (Johnson-Rosebrugh-Wood 2010, Proposition 9). See also the possibility operator.

Proposition

Let C=Set\mathbf{C} = Set. Then every lens L=(S,V,get,put)L = (S, V, \mathrm{get}, \mathrm{put}) is equivalent a “constant complement” lens whose Get is a product projection π 1:C×VV\pi_{1} : C \times V \to V and whose Put is the function π 0,2:C×V×VC×V\pi_{0,2} : C \times V \times V \to C \times V for some set CC.

Proposition

Let C\mathbf{C} be a cartesian closed category. Lenses in C\mathbf{C} are coalgebras for a comonad (the store comonad) the generated by the adjunction:

Generalizations

There are many generalizations of lenses which have been proposed, however they can be broadly classified into those which satisfy analogues of the lens laws, and those without any axioms or laws.

Lenses without laws

  • One generalization considers the lenses from the previous section as monomorphic by contrast to polymorphic lens which go between pairs of types, λ:(S,T)(A,B)\lambda: (S, T) \to (A, B), consisting of a view function, v λ:SAv_{\lambda}: S \to A, and an update function u λ:S×BTu_{\lambda}: S \times B \to T. Without further conditions, these are known as bimorphic lenses. To impose conditions comparable to the lens laws above requires that the types be related.

  • An optic generalizes the way lenses ‘remember’ state from the forward part to the backward part, avoiding the necessity of a cartesian structure by swapping it with a sufficiently rich actegorical context.

Lenses with laws

  • Delta lenses are a generalization which does satisfy laws. Here we have categories SS and VV called the source and view, together with a Get functor g:SVg : S \to V and a function φ:S 0× V 0V 1S 1\varphi \colon S_{0} \times_{V_{0}} V_{1} \to S_{1} which takes a pair (sS,u:gsvV)(s \in S, u : gs \to v \in V) to a morphism

    φ(s,u):sp(s,u)\varphi(s, u) : s \to p(s, u) in SS where p(s,u)=cod(φ(a,u))p(s, u) = cod(\varphi(a, u)) is the Put function. The function φ\varphi must also satisfy three lens laws. When SS and VV are codiscrete categories, delta lenses are equivalent to a lens in Set; see (Johnson-Rosebrugh 2016, Proposition 4).

  • A morphism between directed containers is another kind of generalised lens satisfying laws called update-update lenses; see (Ahman-Uustalu 2017, Section 5). These are equivalent to cofunctors.

References

Journal papers, conference proceedings, and preprints

Blog posts, talk slides, and other material

Last revised on July 11, 2021 at 01:10:35. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.