basic constructions:
strong axioms
further
The most commonly accepted standard foundation of mathematics today is a material set theory commonly known as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice or for short. There are many variations on that theory (including constructive and class-based versions, which are also discussed here).
Accompanying ZFC, especially taking into account the axiom of foundation, is a picture (or ‘ontology’) of material sets forming a cumulative hierarchy organized by an ordinal-valued rank function. This picture (sometimes referred to as the ‘iterative conception’) considers sets as generated by starting at bottom with the empty set and building to higher ranks by applying a power set operation to get to a next successor ordinal rank, and taking unions to get to limit ordinal ranks. This iterative conception finds alternative expression in algebraic set theory.
The first version was developed by Ernst Zermelo in 1908; in 1922, Abraham Fraenkel and Thoralf Skolem independently proposed a precise first-order version with the axiom of replacement; von Neumann added the axiom of foundation in 1925. All of these versions included the axiom of choice, but this was considered controversial for some time; one has merely if it is taken out.
is similar to the class theories NBG (due to John von Neumann, Paul Bernays, and Kurt Gödel) and MK (due to Anthony Morse and John Kelley). The former is a conservative, finitely axiomatisable extension of , while the latter is stronger and cannot be finitely axiomatised (although a conservative extension involving meta-classes could be).
Contemporary set theorists often accept additional large cardinal axioms, which can greatly increase the strength of , far beyond even . Other additional axioms which are sometimes added are the axiom of determinacy (or various weaker versions of it) or the axiom of constructibility. There are also weaker variants of , especially for constructive and predicative mathematics. Then there are alternatives on a different basis, notably NFU (a very impredicative material set theory with a set of all sets) and ETCS (a structural set theory).
(The source for this history, especially the dates, is mostly the English Wikipedia.)
is a simply typed first-order material set theory, with a single type called the cumulative hierarchy and a binary membership predicate on . Every term of in standard is a pure set, which we will call simply a set. A set is said to belong to, be in, be a member of, or be an element of a set if , and set is said to have the member .
There are also variations of ZFC with non-set terms such as urelements and classes. Urelements may be distinguished from sets and classes since they have no elements (although the empty set also has no elements); sets are usually those classes that are themselves elements (members) of sets. Urelements are also called atoms, and with atoms included is sometimes called ZFA or .
Extensionality: If two sets have the same members, then they are equal and themselves members of the same sets. See axiom of extensionality for variations, such as whether this is taken as a definition or an axiomatisation of equality of sets, and how the condition might be strengthened if (10) is left out.
Null Set: There is an empty set: a set with no elements. By (1), it follows that this set is unique; by even the weakest version of (5), it is enough to state the existence of some set. (Analogous remarks apply to axioms (3), (4), (6), (7), and (8), except when (5) is omitted and (4) and (6) are needed to derive it.)
Pairing: If and are sets, then there is a set , the unordered pairing of and , whose elements are precisely those sets equal to or . Between them, (2) and (3) form a nullary/binary pair; the unary version follows from (3), since by (1). The higher finitary versions rely also on (4) (with , etc), so they should probably be stated explicitly as an axiom scheme if (4) is omitted (but nobody seems to do that).
Union: If is a set, then there is a set , the union of , whose elements are precisely the elements of the elements of . It is normal to write for , etc, for , etc. Note that and (using (1) to prove these results), so no special notation is needed for these.
Separation/Specification/Comprehension: Given any predicate in the language of set theory with the chosen free variable of type , if is a set, then there is a set , the subset of given by , whose elements are precisely those elements of such that holds. There are many variations, from Bounded Separation to Full Comprehension, which we should probably describe at axiom of separation; the version listed here is Full Separation. This is an axiom scheme, but it can be made a single axiom in (but not completely in ). Note that (5) follows from (4) and (6) using classical logic, so it is often left out, but it must be included in intuitionistic variations, variations where (6) is omitted or weakened (or where (4) is omitted or weakened, in principle, although that never happens in practice), and variations where (5) itself is strengthened.
Replacement/Collection: Given a predicate with the chosen free variables and of type , if is a set and if for every in there is a unique such that holds, then there is set , the image of under , whose elements are precisely those sets such that there is an element of such that holds; if is a defined term, then we write for . Again there are many variations, from Weak Replacement to Strong Collection, which we should probably describe at axiom of replacement; the one described here is Replacement. This is also an axiom scheme, but it can be made into a single axiom in both and . One could combine this with (5) to produce , but nobody seems to do this.
Power Sets: If is a set, then there is a set , the power set of , whose elements are precisely the subsets of , that is the sets whose elements are all elements of . When using intuitionistic logic, it is possible to accept only a weak version of this, such as Subset Collection or (even weaker) Exponentiation. But in classical logic, Power Sets follows from Exponentiation and the weakest form of (5).
Infinity: There is a set of finite ordinals as pure sets. Normally one states that and whenever , although variations are possible. Using any but the weakest version of (6), it is enough to state that there is a set satisfying Peano's axioms of natural numbers, or even any Dedekind-infinite set. It seems to be uncommon to incorporate (2) into (8), but in principle (8) implies (2).
Choice: If is a set of pairwise disjoint sets, each of which has an element, then there is a set with exactly one element from each element of . Note that this set is not unique, nor can we construct a canonical version which is, so we do not give it any name or notation. This version is the simplest to state in the language of ; see axiom of choice for further discussion and weak versions. It is possible to incorporate (9) into (5) or (6), but this seems to be rare.
Foundation/Regularity/Induction: Given a formula with a chosen free variable of type , if holds whenever holds for every , then holds absolutely. For variations (including the axiom of anti-foundation), see axiom of foundation. This axiom scheme can be made into a single axiom even in itself (although not in versions with intuitionistic logic; in that case it can be made a single axiom only in a class theory).
Zermelo's original version consists of axioms (1–5) and (7–9), in a somewhat imprecise form (which affects the interpretation of 5) of higher-order classical logic.
The modern consists of (1–8) and (10), using first-order classical logic, the strongest form of (6) (that is, Strong Collection, although the standard Replacement is sufficient with classical logic), and the strongest form of (5) possible using only sets and not classes (Full Separation). Since Full Separation follows from Replacement with classical logic, it is often omitted from the list of axioms.
adds (9) and is thus the strongest version without classes or additional axioms. The version originally formulated by Fraenkel and Skolem did not include (10), although the three founders all eventually accepted it.
It is common to take Zermelo set theory () to be without (6), although Zermelo never accepted the first-order formulation, and his axioms did not include the Axiom of Foundation (10). Note that the weakest form (Weak Replacement) of (6) follows from (7) and (5), so it holds even in .
Another variant is bounded Zermelo set theory (), which is like but with only Bounded Separation; this is of interest to category theorists because is equivalent to ETCS.
See also constructive set theory.
The most well-known foundations for constructive mathematics through material set theory are Peter Aczel's constructive Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory () and John Myhill's intuitionistic Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory ().
uses axioms (1–8) and (10), usually weak forms, in intuitionistic logic; specifically, it uses Bounded Separation for (5), Strong Collection for (6), and an intermediate (Subset Collection) form of (7). is simliar, but it uses Full Separation for (5) and the full strength of (7); Myhill's original version uses only Replacement for (6), but Collection (equivalent to Strong Collection using Full Separation) is standard now.
Note that adding (9) to implies excluded middle and so makes . However, some authors like to include a weak form of (9), such as dependent choice or COSHEP.
Mike Shulman's survey of material and structural set theories (Shulman 2018) takes as the most basic form; it consists of (1–4) and the weakest versions (Bounded Separation and Weak Replacement) of (5&6) in intuitionistic logic. Adding (10) gives , adding (8) gives , and adding both gives , constructive pre-Zermelo set theory. Shulman gives systematic notation for other versions, which includes those (constructive and classical) listed above.
Myhill has another version, constructive set theory (); this consists of (1–4), Bounded Separation for (5), Replacement for (6), the weakest (Exponentiation) form of (7), (8), and a weak version (Dependent Choice) of (9). It also uses a variation of the language, with urelements for natural numbers; note that the existence of still follows using (6). This classifies as in Shulman's system if one ignores the use of urelements and strengthens Replacement to Strong Collection.
Morse–Kelley class theory () features both sets and proper classes. This allows it to strengthen (5) to Full Comprehension, since can include quantification over classes; the same holds in (6) and (10), although this does not add any additional strength.
Von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel class theory () uses the same language as , but it still uses only Full Separation for (5). This makes it conservative over and also allows for a finite axiomatisation; we replace the formulas in (5) and (6) with classes, and add some special cases of (5) for subclasses, one for each logical connective. (It is provable that plain , if consistent, cannot be finitely axiomatized in its own first-order language; escapes this conclusion by extending the language with the notion of classes.)
One can also rework all of the weak versions of set theory above into a class theory like , which is conservative over the original set theory. One can also use a class theory like , although this destroys any attempt to use a weak version of (5).
One often adds axioms for large cardinals to . Even (8) can be seen as a large cardinal axiom, stating that exists. These additional axioms are most commonly studied in the context of a material set theory, but they work just as well in a structural set theory.
Note that adding an inaccessible cardinal (commonly considered the smallest sort of large cardinal) to is already stronger than : given an inaccessible cardinal , one can interpret the sets and classes in as the sets in and , respectively. Of course, one can add a large cardinal to to get something even stronger.
It is often convenient to assume that one always has more large cardinals when necessary. You cannot say this in an absolute sense, but you can adopt the axiom that every set belongs to some Grothendieck universe. Adding this axiom to makes Tarski-Grothendieck set theory (). This is not the last word, however; you can make it stronger by adding classes in the style of , or even adding a cardinal which is inaccessible from . In fact, we have barely begun the large cardinals known to modern set theory!
The axiom of constructibility, usually notated “”, is a very strong axiom that can be added to ; it asserts that all sets belong to the constructible universe , which can be “constructed” in a definable way through a transfinite procedure. This notion of “constructible” should not be confused with constructive mathematics; for instance, implies the axiom of choice and thus also excluded middle even with intuitionistic logic. also implies the generalized continuum hypothesis (), which is how Gödel originally proved that was consistent with . However, it is incompatible with the sufficiently large cardinals: the existence of a measurable cardinal implies that . Most contemporary set theorists do not regard as potentially “true.”
The axiom of determinacy () is another axiom that can be added to ; it asserts that a certain class of infinite games is determined (one player or the other has a winning strategy). is inconsistent with the full axiom of choice, although it is consistent with dependent choice. A weaker form of called “projective determinacy” is consistent with and is equiconsistent with certain large cardinal assertions.
The itself, or its negation, could also be regarded as an additional axiom that can be added to . Many set theorists would prefer to find a more “natural” axiom, such as a large cardinal axiom, which implies either or its negation. The equiconsistency of projective determinacy with a large cardinal assertion can be regarded as a step in this direction.
The structural set theory ETCS is equivalent to in that the category of sets in that theory satisfies while the well-founded pure sets in satisfy . This uses (1–4), Bounded Separation for (5), and (7–10), with Weak Replacement following from (5) and (7).
Mike Shulman's SEARC is equivalent to in the same way. , which lacks the axiom of choice, is equivalent to , which is without (10), in a weaker sense of equivalence.
Shulman 2018 is an extensive survey of variations of and variations of (mostly weak ones), showing how these correspond.
Zermelo’s axiomatisation grew out of his reflections on his proofs of the well-ordering theorem (1904/08) and was published in
English versions of the early key texts on set theory by Zermelo, Fraenkel, Skolem, von Neumann et al. can be found in
There are many texts which discuss ZFC and the cumulative hierarchy from a traditional (material) set-theoretic perspective. A good example is
A classification of axioms of variants of , with an eye towards corresponding structural set theories, is
Last revised on May 9, 2023 at 11:24:47. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.