nLab duality

Redirected from "concrete duality".
Duality

Duality

Idea

Instances of “dualities” relating two different, maybe opposing, but to some extent equivalent concepts or phenomena are ubiquitous in mathematics (and in mathematical physics, see at dualities in physics). The term “duality” is widespread and doesn’t have a single crisp meaning, but a rough guiding intuition is of pairs of concepts that are mirror images of one another.

General notions

In terms of general abstract concepts in logic and category theory, instances of dualities might be (and have been) organized as follows.

Abstract/formal/axiomatic duality

Instances here include projective duality, duality in lattice theory, and duality in category theory. In each case, one has a theory whose signature admits a nontrivial involution, in such a way that “dualizing” or applying the involution to any axiom of the theory (but otherwise preserving the logical structure of formulae) results in another theorem of the theory. For example, for the theory of projective planes, the involution swaps points and lines, meets and joins, etc., and for each theorem there is a dual theorem. Similarly, in category theory, the involution swaps the domain and codomain and order of composition, etc., and for any theorem of formal category theory, the corresponding dual statement is also a theorem (because the set of axioms of category theory are closed under taking formal duals).

Such formal duality can also be expressed at the level of models of the theory TT: for each model MM there is a “dual” or “opposite” model M opM^{op} obtained by re-interpreting each formal sort/function/relation of the theory as the dual sort/function/relation. This further induces an involution Mod(T)Mod(T)Mod(T) \to Mod(T) on the category of models. For example, in the case of category theory, this operation CC opC \mapsto C^{op}, mapping a category CC to its opposite category, gives an involution () op:CatCat(-)^{op}: Cat \to Cat on the category Cat of (small) categories, viewing CatCat here as a 1-category. In fact this is the only non-trivial automorphism of Cat, see here).

This involution () op:CatCat(-)^{op}: Cat \to Cat is also known as abstract duality. While the construction is a priori tautologous, any given opposite category often is equivalent to a category known by other means, which makes abstract duality interesting (particularly so in cases of concrete duality, which we discuss next).

Concrete dualities

Instances here include linear duality, Stone duality, Pontryagin duality, and projective inversions with respect to a conic hypersurface. In each such case there is some contravariant process of “homming into” a suitable structure VV called a dualizing object, which in the classical cases of what we will call “perfect duality”, induces an equivalence of categories C opDC^{op} \stackrel{\sim}{\to} D where typically CC is the category of models of one type of concrete structure, and the equivalence maps the formal categorical dual C opC^{op} to a category of models DD consisting of “dual” concrete structures.

In other cases one might not obtain an equivalence or perfect duality, but in any case a contravariant adjoint pair of functors S:CDS: C \to D, T:DCT: D \to C between categories which can be termed a duality of sorts, in that concepts developed in CC are mapped to dual concepts in DD and vice-versa. Quoting (Lawvere-Rosebrugh, chapter 7):

Not every statement will be taken into its formal dual by the process of dualizing with respect to VV, and indeed a large part of the study of mathematics

space vs. quantity

and of logic

theory vs. example

may be considered as the detailed study of the extent to which formal duality and concrete duality into a favorite VV correspond or fail to correspond. (p. 122)

Some examples follow.

  • In linear duality, say for vector spaces over a field kk, the dual of a space WW is W *=hom(W,k)W^\ast = \hom(W, k), the hom of kk-linear maps into kk. This induces a contravariant functor () *:Vect kVect k(-)^\ast: Vect_k \to Vect_k that is adjoint to itself, in that there is a double-dual embedding δ W:WW **\delta_W: W \to W^{\ast\ast} such that

    1 W *=(W *δ W *W ***(δ W) *W *).1_{W^\ast} = (W^\ast \stackrel{\delta_{W^\ast}}{\to} W^{\ast\ast\ast} \stackrel{(\delta_W)^\ast}{\to} W^\ast).

    This becomes a perfect duality if we restrict to finite-dimensional vector spaces, i.e., the contravariant functor () *:Vect fdVect fd(-)^\ast: Vect_{fd} \to Vect_{fd} is adjoint-equivalent to itself (i.e., the covariant functor (() *) op:Vect fdVect fd op((-)^\ast)^{op}: Vect_{fd} \to Vect_{fd}^{op} is left adjoint to () *:Vect fd opVect fd(-)^\ast: Vect_{fd}^{op} \to Vect_{fd} and the adjunction is an adjoint equivalence).

  • More generally, given a (usually symmetric) monoidal closed category 𝒞\mathcal{C}, any object DD induces an operation [,D]:𝒞𝒞 op[-,D] : \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{C}^{op} obtained by forming the internal hom into DD, sending each object to what may be termed its DD-dual object. There is a corresponding double-dual embedding δ C:C[[C,D],D]\delta_C: C \to [ [C, D], D] obtained as the composite

    C[[C,D],C[C,D]][[C,D],[C,D]C][[C,D],D]C \to [ [C, D], C \otimes [C, D]] \to [ [C, D], [C, D] \otimes C] \to [ [C, D], D]

    where the first arrow uses the unit of an adjunction (B)[B,](- \otimes B) \dashv [B, -] where B=[C,D]B = [C, D], the second uses a symmetry isomorphism CBBCC \otimes B \cong B \otimes C, and the third uses the counit of an adjunction (C)[C,](- \otimes C) \dashv [C, -], aka an evaluation map. It may be shown that the contravariant functor () *[,D]:𝒞𝒞(-)^\ast \coloneqq [-, D]: \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{C} is again dual to itself, exactly as in the case of linear duality above, where we have a triangular equation

    1 C *=(δ C) *δ C *1_{C^\ast} = (\delta_C)^\ast \circ \delta_{C^\ast}

    for an adjunction [,D] op[,D][-, D]^{op} \dashv [-, D]. Under certain circumstances, we have perfect duality, i.e., double dualization [[,D],D]:𝒞𝒞[ [-, D], D]: \mathcal{C} \to \mathcal{C} is an equivalence; see dualizing object in a closed category and star-autonomous category. Particular special cases of this may obtain when D=ID = I, the monoidal unit, or even more particularly when every object has a dual object in the sense of monoidal categories; see also compact closed category. On the other hand, there is also a mild generalization of this type of example where we deal with a biclosed monoidal category; here the double dualization will involve both the left and right internal hom.

  • More general still is a concrete duality induced by a dualizing object. In this case one is given a pair of categories together with underlying-set functors

    U:𝒞Set,V:𝒟SetU: \mathcal{C} \to Set, \qquad V: \mathcal{D} \to Set

    (and often when one says “concrete”, one intends that these functors be faithful as well, so that 𝒞,𝒟\mathcal{C}, \mathcal{D} can be viewed as “sets with structure”; see stuff, structure, property). The concrete duality consists of a pair of objects C𝒞,D𝒟C \in \mathcal{C}, D \in \mathcal{D} together with an isomorphism ω:UCVD\omega: U C \cong V D, such that the contravariant homs hom(,C):C opSet\hom(-, C): C^{op} \to Set and hom(,D):D opSet\hom(-, D): D^{op} \to Set lift to a contravariant adjunction between CC and DD, in the sense described here. Frequently in practice, such concrete dualities are “naturally represented” in the sense described here, involving certain lifts adapted from the theory of topological concrete categories.

Again, in all of these examples, one can consider the further condition of “perfect duality” where the units and counits of the (lifted) adjunctions are isomorphisms.

Adjunctions

Perhaps the loosest general notion of “duality” is that of adjunction, as in pairs of adjoint functors (Lambek 81). Here one may omit any concretizations via functors to SetSet, or even for that matter any explicit mention of opposite categories, and just work at the level of abstract categories themselves.

Nevertheless, many adjunctions come packaged in “dual pairs”. A famous slogan from Categories for the Working Mathematician is that “all concepts are Kan extensions”, and in that light the dual pairs are instances of the general dual pair “(right Kan extension, left Kan extension)” which are formal duals in the axiomatic sense described earlier. Via the many incarnations of universal constructions in category theory, we have for example

When the adjoint functors are monads and hence modalities, then adjointness between them has been argued to specifically express the concept of duality of opposites.

Again, adjunctions and specifically dual adjunctions (“Galois connections”) may be thought of as generalized dualities, more general than “perfect duality” which involves equivalences between categories (“Galois correspondences”). However, it should also be noted that any such adjunction (or dual adjunction) restricts to a maximal (dual) equivalence between subcategories, by considering objects where the appropriate units and counits are isomorphisms. This generalizes the manner by which any Galois connection induces a Galois correspondence (where in this special case, one need only take the images of the poset maps which constitute the connection).

Examples

Dualizing objects

Of particular interest are concrete dualities between concrete categories C,DC, D, i.e. categories equipped with faithful functors

f:CSet f : C \to Set

to Set, which are represented by objects aCa \in C, a^D\hat a \in D with the same underlying set f(a)=f^(a^)f(a) = \hat f(\hat a). Such objects are known as dualizing objects.

References

Discussion of duality specifically in homological algebra and stable homotopy theory with emphasis on the concept of dualizing object in a closed category (and the induced Umkehr maps etc.) is in

See also

Last revised on July 11, 2023 at 08:49:45. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.