nLab adjoint modality

Redirected from "opposite".
Contents

Contents

Idea

The concept of adjunction as such expresses a duality. The stronger concept of an adjoint cylinder or adjoint modality is specifically an adjunction between idempotent (co-)monads and is meant to express specifically a duality between opposites.

In terms of the corresponding adjoint triple of (co-)reflections and localizations the concept was suggested in (Lawvere 91, p. 7, Lawvere 94, p. 11) to capture the phenomena of “Unity and Identity of Opposites” as they appear informally in Georg Hegel‘s Science of Logic. (One might therefore say the notion is meant to capture the idea of “dialectic”, though there is some debate as to whether Hegel’s somewhat mythical “creation out of paradox” should really go by this term, see this Wikipeda entry ).

In terms of adjoint pairs of modal operators in the context of modal logic/modal type theory and thought of as Galois connections the concept appears in (Reyes-Zolfaghari 91). Further developments along these lines include (DJK 14).

Definition

In (Lawvere 94) an adjoint cylinder is defined to be an adjoint triple such that the outer two adjoints are full and faithful functors. This means equivalently that the induced adjoint pair on the codomain of these inclusions consists of an idempotent monad and comonad (adjoint monads). One may also consider the situation where the middle functor of the adjoint triple is fully faithful, hence one has adjoint modal operators either of the form

U:modalitycomodality, U \;\colon\; modality \dashv comodality \,,

or of the form

U:comodalitymodality. U \;\colon\; comodality \dashv modality \,.

A category equipped with an adjoint modality of the second form is called a category of being in (Lawvere 91). If the category is a topos then this is also called a level of a topos.

Given any such, we may say that the “unity” expressed by the two opposites is exhibited by the canonical natural transformation

UX:comodalX X modalX opposite1 unity opposite2 U X \;\colon\; \array{ comodal X &\longrightarrow& X &\longrightarrow& modal X \\ opposite\;1 && unity && opposite\;2 }

which is the composite of the counit of the comodality and the unit of the modality (Lawvere-Rosebrugh 03, p. 245).

If for two levels the next one contains the modal types of the idempotent comonad of the former, then Lawvere speaks of “Aufhebung” (see there for more).

One can consider longer sequences of such adjoints of co/modalities, but the longer they get, the less likely they are to be non-trivial. The longest that still has good nontrivial models seems to be adjoint triples of modalities. Of these there is then similarly either the form

modalitycomodalitymodality modality \dashv comodality \dashv modality

(the “Yin triple”) as for instance in the definition of cohesion and

comodalitymodalitycomodality comodality \dashv modality \dashv comodality

(the “Yang triple”) as for instance in the definition of differential cohesion.

Since adjoint triples are equivalently adjunctions of adjunctions (Licata-Shulman, section 5), it is suggestive to denote these as

\array{ \lozenge &\dashv& \bigcirc \\ \bot && \bot \\ \bigcirc &\dashv& \Box }

Examples

Simple illustrative examples

The following simple illustrative example of an adjunction of the form \Box \dashv \bigcirc has been suggested in (Lawvere 00).

Example

(even and odd integers)

Regard the integers as a preordered set (,)(\mathbb{Z}, \leq) in the canonical way, and thus as a thin category.

Consider the full subcategory inclusions

(,) even (,) n 2nAAAAA(,) odd (,) n 2n+1 \array{ (\mathbb{Z}, \leq ) & \overset{even}{\hookrightarrow}& (\mathbb{Z},\leq) \\ n &\mapsto & 2 n } \phantom{AAAAA} \array{ (\mathbb{Z}, \leq ) & \overset{odd}{\hookrightarrow}& (\mathbb{Z},\leq) \\ n &\mapsto & 2 n + 1 }

of the even and the odd integers, as well as the functor

(,) /2 (,) n n/2 \array{ (\mathbb{Z}, \leq ) & \overset{\lfloor-/2\rfloor}{\longrightarrow}& (\mathbb{Z},\leq) \\ n &\mapsto& \lfloor n/2 \rfloor }

which sends any nn to the floor n/2\lfloor n/2 \rfloor of n/2n/2, hence to the largest integer which is smaller or equal to the rational number n/2n/2.

These functors form an adjoint triple

even/2odd even \;\dashv\; \lfloor -/2 \rfloor \;\dashv\; odd

and hence induce an adjoint modality

EvenOdd Even \;\dashv\; Odd

on (,)(\mathbb{Z}, \leq) with

  1. Even2/2Even \coloneqq 2 \lfloor -/2 \rfloor sending any integer to its “even floor value”

  2. Odd2/2+1Odd \coloneqq 2 \lfloor -/2 \rfloor + 1 sending any integer to its “odd ceiling value”.

Proof

Observe that for all nn \in \mathbb{Z} we have

2n/2ϵ nnη n2n/2+1, 2 \lfloor n/2 \rfloor \overset{ \epsilon_n }{\leq} n \overset{ \eta_n }{\leq} 2 \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \,,

where the first inequality is an equality precisely if nn is even, while the second is an equality precisely if nn is odd. Hence this provides a candidate unit η\eta and counit ϵ\epsilon.

Hence by this characterization of adjoint functors

  1. the adjunction /2odd\lfloor -/2 \rfloor \dashv odd is equivalent to the condition that

    for every n2k+1n \leq 2 k + 1 we have 2n/2+12k+12 \lfloor n/2 \rfloor + 1 \leq 2 k + 1;

  2. the adjunction even/2even \dashv \lfloor -/2 \rfloor is equivalent to the condition that

    for every 2kn2k \leq n we have 2k2n/22k \leq 2 \lfloor n/2 \rfloor ,

which is readily seen to be the case

In the same vein there is an example for an adjunction of the form \bigcirc \dashv \Box:

Example

Consider the inclusion ι:(,<)(,<)\iota \colon (\mathbb{Z}, \lt) \hookrightarrow (\mathbb{R}, \lt) of the integers into the real numbers, both regarded as linear orders. This inclusion has a left adjoint given by ceiling and a right adjoint given by floor.

The composite CeilingιceilingCeiling \coloneqq \iota ceiling is an idempotent monad and the composite FloorιfloorFloor \coloneqq \iota floor is an idempotent comonad on \mathbb{R}. Both express a moment of integrality in an real number, but in opposite ways, each real number xx\in \mathbb{R} sits in between its floor and celling

Floor(x)xCeiling(x). Floor(x) \leq x \leq Ceiling(x) \,.

Indeed the moments form an adjunction

CeilingFloor. Ceiling \dashv Floor \,.

Werden : Nichts \dashv Sein

For H\mathbf{H} a topos/(∞,1)-topos consider the “initial topos”, the terminal category *Sh()\ast \simeq Sh(\emptyset) (category of sheaves on the empty site).

There is then an adjoint triple

H** \mathbf{H} \stackrel {\overset{\vdash \varnothing}{\longleftarrow}} {\stackrel{\overset{}{\longrightarrow}} {\underset{\vdash \ast}{\longleftarrow}}} \ast

given by including the initial object \varnothing and the terminal object *\ast into H\mathbf{H}, respectively.

In the type theory of H\mathbf{H} this corresponds to the adjoint pair of modalities

* \varnothing \dashv \ast

which are constant on the initial object/terminal object, respectively.

The induced unit of an adjunction transformation is

X* \array{ \varnothing \longrightarrow X \longrightarrow \ast }

hence the unique factorization of the unique function *\varnothing \longrightarrow \ast through any other type.

Looking through (Hegel 1812, vol 1, book 1, section 1, chapter 1) one might call \emptyset “nothing”, call *\ast “being” and then call this unity of opposites “becoming”. In particular in §174 of Science of Logic it says

there is nothing which is not an intermediate state between being and nothing

which seems to be well-captured by the above unity transformation.

Quantity : discreteness \dashv continuity

The adjoint modality in a local topos is that given by flat modality \dashv sharp modality

. \flat \dashv \sharp \,.

Capturing discrete objects/codiscrete objects.

The corresponding unity transformation is

XXX \flat X \longrightarrow X \longrightarrow \sharp X

According to (Lawvere 94, p. 6) this unity captures the duality that in a set all elements are distinct and yet indistinguishable, an apparent paradox that may be traced back to Georg Cantor.

Looking through Hegel’s Science of Logic at On discreteness and repulsion one can see that matches with what Hegel calls

(par 398) Quantity is the unity of these moments of continuity and discreteness

X X X momentofdiscreteness momentofcontinuity \array{ \flat X &\longrightarrow& X &\longrightarrow& \sharp X \\ {moment\;of \atop discreteness} && && {moment\;of \atop continuity} }

Continuum : repulsion \dashv cohesion

For H\mathbf{H} a cohesive topos/cohesive (∞,1)-topos the shape modality \dashv flat modality constitute an adjoint cylinder

ʃ. &#643; \dashv \flat \,.

The corresponding unity-transformation is the points-to-pieces transform

XXʃX \array{ \flat X \longrightarrow X \longrightarrow &#643; X }

Looking through (Hegel 1812, vol 1, book 1, section 2, chapter 1) one might call \flat “repulsion”, call ʃ&#643; “attraction”/“cohesion” and then call this unity of opposites “continuum”. Indeed, by the discussion at cohesive topos, this does quite well capture the geometric notion of continuum geometry.

Infinitesimal Continuum : infin. repulsion \dashv infinit. cohesion

For H\mathbf{H} equipped moreover with differential cohesion, there is the infinitesimal version of shape modality \dashv flat modality namely the adjoint modality

infinitesimal shape modality\dashv infinitesimal flat modality

&. \Im \dashv \& \,.

The corresponding unity-transformation is the

&XXX \array{ \& X \longrightarrow X \longrightarrow \Im X }

maps from the coefficients for crystalline cohomology to the de Rham space of types XX, where all infinitesimal neighbour points are identified.

In view of the above the unity exhibited here is clearly to be called the “infinitesimal continuum”.

Cohesive sets

The combination of the above two examples of Continuum and Quantity is an adjoint triple of modalities

ʃ &#643; \;\dashv\; \flat \;\dashv\; \sharp

shape modality\dashv flat modality \dashv sharp modality

characteristic of a cohesive topos.

Skeleta and Co-Skeleta

simplicial skeleton\dashv simplicial coskeleton

Formal completion \dashv Torsion approximation

For AA a commutative ring or more generally an E-∞ ring and 𝔞π 0A\mathfrak{a}\subset \pi_0 A a suitable ideal, then 𝔞\mathfrak{a}-adic completion and 𝔞\mathfrak{a}-torsion approximation form an adjoint modality on AMModA MMod the stable (∞,1)-category of ∞-modules AMod A Mod_\infty over AA.

(𝔞\mathfrak{a}-adic completion) \dashv (𝔞\mathfrak{a}-torsion approximation)

Proposition

Let AA be an E-∞ ring and let 𝔞π 0A\mathfrak{a} \subset \pi_0 A be a finitely generated ideal in its underlying commutative ring.

Then there is an adjoint triple of adjoint (∞,1)-functors

AMod 𝔞comp opAMod 𝔞tors op 𝔞Π 𝔞 AMod op \array{ \underoverset{ A Mod_{\mathfrak{a}comp}^{op}} {A Mod_{\mathfrak{a}tors}^{op}} {\simeq} &\stackrel{\overset{\Pi_{\mathfrak{a}}}{\longleftarrow}}{\stackrel{\hookrightarrow}{\underset{\flat_{\mathfrak{a}}}{\longleftarrow}}}& A Mod^{op} }

where

Proof

This is effectively the content of (Lurie “Proper morphisms”, section 4):

  • the existence of Π 𝔞\Pi_{\mathfrak{a}} is corollary 4.1.16 and remark 4.1.17

  • the existence of 𝔞\flat_{\mathfrak{a}} is lemma 4.2.2 there;

  • the equivalence of sub-\infty-categories is proposition 4.2.5 there.

See at fracture theorem for more.

Fermions and supergeometry

On super smooth infinity-groupoids there is an adjoint modality deriving from the adjoint triple relating plain algebra and superalgebra. The right adjoint deserves to be called the bosonic modality (“body”), hence its left adjoint the fermionic modality. This expresses the presence of supergeometry/fermions, hence ultimately the Pauli exclusion principle. Following PN§290 this unity of opposites might hence be called “asunderness”.

Totally distributive categories

For 𝒦\mathcal{K} a totally distributive category it induces on its category of presheaves an adjoint modality whose right adjoint is the Yoneda embedding YY postcomposed with its left adjoint XX.

Recollements

See at recollement.

References

Traditional

The concept of dialectical reasoning is usually attributed to

See

Hegel in his History of Philosophy writes that dialectic begins with Zeno (one of the characters in that dialogue).

This is much amplified and expanded in

The origins of its proposed formalization in category theory are recalled in

  • Joachim Lambek, The Influence of Heraclitus on Modern Mathematics, In Scientific Philosophy Today: Essays in Honor of Mario Bunge, edited by Joseph Agassi and Robert S Cohen, 111–21. Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Co. (1982)

See also

In terms of adjoint triples of (co-)reflections and localizations

Conceived of in terms of adjoint triples of (co-)reflections and localizations the concept appears in

In terms of adjoint pairs of modal operators

In terms of adjoint pairs of modal operators and hence of Galois connections, the concept appears in

  • Gonzalo Reyes, H. Zolfaghari, Topos-theoretic approaches to modality, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 1488 (1991), 359-378.

  • Gonzalo Reyes, A topos-theoretic approach to reference and modality, Notre Dame J. Formal Logic Volume 32, Number 3 (1991), 359-391 (Euclid)

with further developments in

  • M. Sadrzadeh, R. Dyckho, Positive logic with adjoint modalities: Proof theory, semantics and reasoning about information, Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science 249, 451-470, 2009, in Proceedings of the 25th Conference on Mathematical Foundations of Programming Semantics (MFPS 2009).

  • Claudio Hermida, section 3.3. of A categorical outlook on relational modalities and simulations, 2010 (pdf)

  • Wojciech Dzik, Jouni Järvinen, Michiro Kondo, Characterising intermediate tense logics in terms of Galois connections (arXiv:1401.7646)

Formalization specifically in modal type theory is in

For an overview of the role of adjunctions in modal logic see:

  • M. Menni, C. Smith, Modes of Adjointness , J. Philos. Logic 43 no.3-4 (2014) pp.365-391.

Examples

Last revised on May 17, 2023 at 10:14:22. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.