nLab internal category

Redirected from "internal nerve".
Contents

Contents

Idea

The notion of a category can be formulated internal to any other category with enough pullbacks.

By regarding groups as pointed connected (delooping) groupoids, this generalizes the notion of internal groups.

An ordinary small category is a category internal to Set.

There is a more general notion of an internal category in a monoidal category, where the pullbacks are replaced by cotensor products.

Definition

Internal category

Let AA be a category with pullbacks. A category internal to AA consists of

  • an object of objects C 0AC_0 \in A;

  • an object of morphisms C 1AC_1 \in A;

together with

such that the following diagrams commute, expressing the usual category laws:

  • laws specifying the source and target of identity morphisms:
C 0 e C 1 1 s C 0C 0 e C 1 1 t C 0 \array{ C_0 & \overset{e}{\longrightarrow} & C_1 \\ {} & \mathllap{{}_{1}}\searrow & \big\downarrow \mathrlap{{}^{s}} \\ {} & {} & C_0 } \quad\quad\quad\quad \array{ C_0 & \overset{e}{\longrightarrow} & C_1 \\ {} & \mathllap{{}_{1}}\searrow & \big\downarrow \mathrlap{{}^{t}} \\ {} & {} & C_0 }
  • laws specifying the source and target of composite morphisms:
C 1× C 0C 1 c C 1 p 1 s C 1 s C 0C 1× C 0C 1 c C 1 p 2 t C 1 t C 0 \array{ C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1 & \overset{c}{\longrightarrow} & C_1 \\ \mathllap{{}^{p_1}}\big\downarrow & {} & \big\downarrow \mathrlap{{}^{s}} \\ C_1 & \underset{s}{\longrightarrow} & C_0 } \quad\quad\quad\quad \array{ C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1 & \overset{c}{\longrightarrow} & C_1 \\ \mathllap{{}^{p_2}}\big\downarrow & {} & \big\downarrow\mathrlap{{}^{t}} \\ C_1 & \underset{t}{\longrightarrow} & C_0 }
  • the left and right unit laws for composition of morphisms:
C 0× C 0C 1 e× C 01 C 1× C 0C 1 1× C 0e C 1× C 0C 0 p 2 c p 1 C 1 \array{ C_0 \times_{C_0} C_1 & \stackrel{e \times_{C_0} 1}{\to} & C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1 & \stackrel{1 \times_{C_0} e}{\leftarrow} & C_1 \times_{C_0} C_0 \\ {} & {}^{p_2}\searrow & \downarrow^{c} & \swarrow^{p_1} & {} \\ {} & {} & C_1 & {} & {} }

The relevant pullbacks and uniquely induced isomorphisms are formed as below:

C 1× C 0C 1 p 2 C 1 p 1 s C 1 t C 0 \array{ C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1 & \overset{p_2}{\longrightarrow} & C_1 \\ \mathllap{{}^{p_1}}\big\downarrow & {} & \big\downarrow \mathrlap{{}^{s}} \\ C_1 & \underset{t}{\longrightarrow} & C_0 }

Notice that inherent to this definition is the assumption that the pullbacks involved actually exist. This holds automatically when the ambient category AA has finite limits, but there are some important examples such as A=A =\, Diff where this is not the case. Here it is helpful to assume simply that ss and tt have all pullbacks; in the case of DiffDiff this occurs if they are submersions.

Internal groupoid

A groupoid internal to AA is all of the above

  • with a morphism

    C 1iC 1 C_1 \stackrel{i}{\to} C_1
  • such that

    t=(C 1iC 1sC 0),s=(C 1iC 1tC 0). t = ( C_1 \stackrel{i}{\to} C_1 \stackrel{s}{\to} C_0 ),\;\;\;\; s = ( C_1 \stackrel{i}{\to} C_1 \stackrel{t}{\to} C_0 ).
  • and

    C 1 diag C 1 t× C 0 tC 1 Id×i C 1 t× C 0 sC 1 s c C 0 e C 1 \array{ C_1 &\stackrel{diag}{\to}& C_1\;{}_t \times_{C_0}{}_t C_1 &\stackrel{Id \times i}{\to}& C_1\;{}_t \times_{C_0}{}_s C_1 \\ \downarrow^s &&&& \; \downarrow^c \\ C_0 &&\stackrel{e}{\to}&& C_1 }
  • and

    C 1 diag C 1 s× C 0 sC 1 i×Id C 1 t× C 0 sC 1 t c C 0 e C 1 \array{ C_1 &\stackrel{diag}{\to}& C_1\;{}_s \times_{C_0}{}_s C_1 &\stackrel{i \times Id}{\to}& C_1\;{}_t \times_{C_0}{}_s C_1 \\ \downarrow^t &&&& \; \downarrow^c \\ C_0 &&\stackrel{e}{\to}&& C_1 }

Internal functors

Functors between internal categories are defined in a similar fashion. See functor. But if the ambient category does not satisfy the axiom of choice it is often better to use anafunctors instead; this makes sense when CC is a superextensive site.

Alternative definition

If AA has all pullbacks, then we can form the bicategory Span(A)Span(A) of spans in AA. A category in AA is precisely a monad in Span(A)Span(A). The underlying 1-cell is given by the span (s,t):C 0C 1C 0(s,t) : C_0 \leftarrow C_1 \to C_0, and the pullback C 1× C 0C 1C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1 is the vertex of the composite span (s,t)(s,t)(s,t) \circ (s,t). The morphisms ee and cc are required to be morphisms of spans, which is equivalent to imposing the source and target axioms above. Finally the unit and associativity axioms for monads imply those above.

This approach makes it easy to define the notion of internal profunctor.

Internal nerve

The notion of nerve of a small category can be generalised to give an internal nerve construction. For a small category, DD, its nerve, N(D)N(D), is a simplicial set whose set of nn-simplices is the set of sequences of composable morphisms of length nn in DD. This set can be given by a (multiple) pullback of copies of D 1D_1. That description will carry across to give a nerve construction for an internal category.

If CC is an internal category in some category AA, (which thus has, at least, the pullbacks required for the constructions to make sense),its nerve N(C)N(C) (or if more precision is needed N int(C)N_{int}(C), or similar) is the simplicial object in AA with

  • N(C) 0=C 0N(C)_0 = C_0, the ‘object of objects’ of CC;
  • N(C) 1=C 1N(C)_1 = C_1, the ‘object of arrows’ of CC;
  • N(C) 2=C 1× C 0C 1N(C)_2 = C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1 the object of composable pairs of arrows of CC;
  • N(C) 3=C 1× C 0C 1× C 0C 1N(C)_3 = C_1 \times_{C_0} C_1\times_{C_0} C_1, the object of composable triples of arrows;

and so on. Face and degeneracy morphisms are induced from the structural moprhisms of CC in a fairly obvious way.

Internal functors between internal categories induce simplicial morphisms between the corresponding nerves.

Internal category in homotopy type theory

Discussion in homotopy type theory is at internal category in homotopy type theory.

Higher internal categories

One can also look at this in higher category theory and consider internal n-categories. See

The general concept is that of an ( n × k ) (n \times k) -category, which is an nn-category internal to a kk-category.

Examples

A small category is a category internal to Set. In this case, C 0C_0 is a set of objects and C 1C_1 is a set of morphisms and the pullback is a subset of the Cartesian product.

Historically, the motivating example was (apparently) the notion of Lie groupoids: a small Lie groupoid is a groupoid internal to the category Diff of smooth manifolds. This generalises immediately to a smooth category?. Similarly, a topological groupoid is a groupoid internal to Top. (Warning: the term ‘topological category’ usually means a topological concrete category, an unrelated notion. Sometimes a ‘topological category’ is defined to be a TopTop-enriched category, which is a special case of the internal definition if it is interpreted strictly and the collection of objects is small.) In these examples, C 0C_0 is a “space of objects” and C 1C_1 a “space of morphisms”.

Further examples:

Properties

In a cartesian closed category

If the ambient (finitely complete) category E\mathbf{E} is a cartesian closed category, then the category Cat(E)Cat(\mathbf{E}) of categories internal to E\mathbf{E} is also cartesian closed. This was proved twice by Charles and Andrée (under her maiden name Bastiani) Ehresmann using generalised sketches, or may be proven directly as follows (see also Johnstone, remark after B2.3.15):

Theorem

Let E\mathbf{E} be a finitely complete cartesian closed category. Then the category Cat(E)Cat(\mathbf{E}) of internal categories in EE is also finitely complete and cartesian closed.

Proof

First suppose E\mathbf{E} is finitely complete. Then, since Cat(E)Cat(\mathbf{E}) is the category of models for a limit sketch in EE, it follows that Cat(E)Cat(\mathbf{E}) is also finitely complete.

Now suppose that E\mathbf{E} is finitely complete and cartesian closed. Let Δ 3\Delta_3 denote the category of nonempty ordinals up to and including the ordinal with 4 elements. We have a full and faithful embedding

N:Cat(E)E Δ 3 opN \colon Cat(\mathbf{E}) \to \mathbf{E}^{\Delta_3^{op}}

where the codomain category is cartesian closed. Indeed, the exponential of two objects FF, GG in E Δ 3 op\mathbf{E}^{\Delta_3^{op}} may be computed as an E\mathbf{E}-enriched end

G F(m)= n f:nmG(n) F(n)G^F(m) = \int_n \prod_{f \colon n \to m} G(n)^{F(n)}

when evaluated at mOb(E Δ 3 op)m \in Ob(\mathbf{E}^{\Delta_3^{op}}), as is easily checked (see for instance here); note that this end is a finite limit diagram since Δ 3\Delta_3 is finite.

If CC, DD are internal categories in E\mathbf{E}, seen as functors Δ 3 opE\Delta_3^{op} \to \mathbf{E}, the exponential NC NDN C^{N D} defines the exponential in Cat(E)Cat(\mathbf{E}). To see this, it suffices to check that NC NDN C^{N D}, as defined by the end formula above, is a category BB, i.e., is in the essential image of the nerve functor. For in that case, we have natural isomorphisms

F×DCinCat(E)NF×NDN(F×D)NCinE Δ 3 opNFNC NDinE Δ 3 opFBinCat(E)\frac{ \frac{F \times D \to C \;\;\;\text{in}\; Cat(\mathbf{E})} {N F \times N D \cong N(F \times D) \to N C \;\;\;\text{in}\; \mathbf{E}^{\Delta_3^{op}}}} {\frac{N F \to N C^{N D} \;\;\;\text{in}\; \mathbf{E}^{\Delta_3^{op}}} {F \to B \;\;\;\text{in}\; Cat(\mathbf{E})}}

whence BB satisfies the universal property required of an exponential.

Objects in the essential image of the nerve NN are characterized as functors Δ 3 opE\Delta_3^{op} \to \mathbf{E} which take intervalic joins in Δ 3\Delta_3 to pullbacks in E\mathbf{E}, as given precisely by the Segal conditions. The remainder of the proof is then finished by the following lemma.

Lemma

If C:Δ 3 opEC \colon \Delta_3^{op} \to \mathbf{E} satisfies the Segal conditions and X:Δ 3 opEX \colon \Delta_3^{op} \to \mathbf{E} is any functor, then C XC^X also satisfies the Segal conditions.

Proof

For any XX we have the formula

C X(m)= kHom(Xk, f:nk g:nmC(n)).C^X(m) = \int_k Hom(X k, \prod_{f \colon n \to k} \prod_{g \colon n \to m} C(n)).

Since the enriched end and the internal hom-functor Hom(Xk,)Hom(X k, -) both preserve pullbacks, we are reduced to checking that

  • If CC satisfies the Segal conditions, then so does
    f:nk g:nmC(n)\prod_{f \colon n \to k} \prod_{g \colon n \to m} C(n)

    as a functor Δ 3 opE\Delta_3^{op} \to \mathbf{E} in the argument mm (for each fixed kk).

Note that the displayed statement is a proposition in the language of finitely complete categories (i.e., in finitary essentially algebraic logic). Since hom-functors E(e,):ESet\mathbf{E}(e, -) \colon \mathbf{E} \to Set jointly preserve and reflect the validity of such propositions, it suffices to prove it for the case where E=Set\mathbf{E} = Set. But this is classical elementary category theory; it says precisely that if CC is a small (ordinary) category, then the usual functor categories C 2C^{\mathbf{2}}, C 3C^{\mathbf{3}} are equivalently described by exponentials of (truncated) simplicial sets. This completes the proof.

In a topos

If the ambient category is a topos, then with the right kind of notion of internal functor, the internal groupoids form the corresponding (2,1)-topos of groupoid-valued stacks and the internal categories form the corresponding 2-topos of category-valued stacks/2-sheaves.

For the precise statement see at 2-topos – In terms of internal categories

Internalization versus enrichment

See internalization versus enrichment.

References

The general definition of internal categories seems to have first been formulated in:

  • Alexander Grothendieck, p. 106 (9 of 21) of: FGA Techniques de construction et théorèmes d’existence en géométrie algébrique III: préschémas quotients, Séminaire Bourbaki: années 1960/61, exposés 205-222, Séminaire Bourbaki, no. 6 (1961), Exposé no. 212, (numdam:SB_1960-1961__6__99_0, pdf, English translation: web version)

following the general principle of internalization formulated in

  • Alexander Grothendieck, p. 370 (3 of 23) in: FGA Technique de descente et théorèmes d’existence en géométrie algébriques. II: Le théorème d’existence en théorie formelle des modules, Séminaire Bourbaki : années 1958/59 - 1959/60, exposés 169-204, Séminaire Bourbaki, no. 5 (1960), Exposé no. 195 (numdam:SB_1958-1960__5__369_0, pdf, English translation: web version)

The concept of topological groupoids and Lie groupoids goes back to

  • Charles Ehresmann, Catégories topologiques et categories différentiables, Colloque de Géométrie différentielle globale, Bruxelles, C.B.R.M., (1959) pp. 137-150 (pdf, zbMath:0205.28202)

and their understanding as categories internal to TopologicalSpaces and to SmoothManifolds is often attributed to

but it seems that the definition is not actually contained in there, certainly not in its simple and widely understood form due to Grothendieck 61.

The observation that (internal) categories are monads in the bicategory of spans:

  • Marta Bunge, Categories of set valued functors, PhD thesis, University of Pennsylvania (1966) [pdf]

  • Jean Bénabou, §5.4.3 in: Introduction to Bicategories, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 47 Springer (1967) 1-77 [doi:10.1007/BFb0074299]

  • Jean Celeyrette, Catégories internes et fibrations & Cohomologie de Gel’fand-Fuks, PhD thesis, Paris (1975) [pdf]

On category-valued stacks (2-sheaves) as internal categories in a sheaf topos, and on weak equivalences of internal categories:

Establishing the canonical model structure for internal categories in a Grothendieck topos:

and in the further generality of finitely complete categories:

Review of the basics of internal categories:

The notion of internal profunctors between internal categories (without recalling their definition) is due to:

  • Jean Bénabou, §5.1 of: Les distributeurs, Université Catholique de Louvain, Institut de Mathématique Pure et Appliquée, rapport 33 (1973) [pdf, pdf]

An early textbook account with explicit definitions of internal categories, internal functors and internal profunctors:

  • Peter Johnstone, Chapter 2 of: Topos theory, London Math. Soc. Monographs 10, Acad. Press 1977, xxiii+367 pp. (Available as Dover Reprint, Mineola 2014)

Further textbook accounts:

and with emphasis on an ambient topos theory:

Survey and introduction with an eye towards Lie theory:

The original proofs that the category of internal categories is cartesian closed when the ambient category is finitely complete and cartesian closed are in

See also:

Discussion in terms of monads in spans:

  • Renato Betti, Formal theory of internal categories, Le Matematiche Vol. LI (1996) Supplemento 35-52 pdf

Discussion of the canonical model structure on categories of internal categories:

Discussion of localization and anafunctors between internal categories:

An old discussion on variants of internal categories, crossed modules and 2-groups is archived here.

A good general reference:

  • Adrian Miranda: Internal categories, MSc thesis, Macquarie University (2018) [url, pdf],

Last revised on October 1, 2024 at 21:49:14. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.