internalization and categorical algebra
algebra object (associative, Lie, …)
category object in an (∞,1)-category, groupoid object
The notion of a category can be formulated internal to any other category with enough pullbacks.
By regarding groups as pointed connected (delooping) groupoids, this generalizes the notion of internal groups.
An ordinary small category is a category internal to Set.
There is a more general notion of an internal category in a monoidal category, where the pullbacks are replaced by cotensor products.
Let be a category with pullbacks. A category internal to consists of
together with
a composition morphism ;
such that the following diagrams commute, expressing the usual category laws:
The relevant pullbacks and uniquely induced isomorphisms are formed as below:
Notice that inherent to this definition is the assumption that the pullbacks involved actually exist. This holds automatically when the ambient category has finite limits, but there are some important examples such as Diff where this is not the case. Here it is helpful to assume simply that and have all pullbacks; in the case of this occurs if they are submersions.
A groupoid internal to is all of the above
with a morphism
such that
and
and
Functors between internal categories are defined in a similar fashion. See functor. But if the ambient category does not satisfy the axiom of choice it is often better to use anafunctors instead; this makes sense when is a superextensive site.
If has all pullbacks, then we can form the bicategory of spans in . A category in is precisely a monad in . The underlying 1-cell is given by the span , and the pullback is the vertex of the composite span . The morphisms and are required to be morphisms of spans, which is equivalent to imposing the source and target axioms above. Finally the unit and associativity axioms for monads imply those above.
This approach makes it easy to define the notion of internal profunctor.
The notion of nerve of a small category can be generalised to give an internal nerve construction. For a small category, , its nerve, , is a simplicial set whose set of -simplices is the set of sequences of composable morphisms of length in . This set can be given by a (multiple) pullback of copies of . That description will carry across to give a nerve construction for an internal category.
If is an internal category in some category , (which thus has, at least, the pullbacks required for the constructions to make sense),its nerve (or if more precision is needed , or similar) is the simplicial object in with
and so on. Face and degeneracy morphisms are induced from the structural moprhisms of in a fairly obvious way.
Internal functors between internal categories induce simplicial morphisms between the corresponding nerves.
Discussion in homotopy type theory is at internal category in homotopy type theory.
One can also look at this in higher category theory and consider internal n-categories. See
The general concept is that of an -category, which is an -category internal to a -category.
A small category is a category internal to Set. In this case, is a set of objects and is a set of morphisms and the pullback is a subset of the Cartesian product.
Historically, the motivating example was (apparently) the notion of Lie groupoids: a small Lie groupoid is a groupoid internal to the category Diff of smooth manifolds. This generalises immediately to a smooth category?. Similarly, a topological groupoid is a groupoid internal to Top. (Warning: the term ‘topological category’ usually means a topological concrete category, an unrelated notion. Sometimes a ‘topological category’ is defined to be a -enriched category, which is a special case of the internal definition if it is interpreted strictly and the collection of objects is small.) In these examples, is a “space of objects” and a “space of morphisms”.
Further examples:
A category internal to Set is a small category
A groupoid internal to definable sets is a definable groupoid.
A groupoid internal to a category of presheaves is a presheaf of groupoids.
A groupoid internal to the opposite of CRing is a commutative Hopf algebroid.
A pointed one-object category internal to Ho(Top) is an H-monoid?.
A pointed one-object groupoid internal to Ho(Top) is an H-group.
A cocategory in is a category internal to .
A double category is a category internal to Cat.
A double bicategory is a category internal to Bicat (in a suitably weak sense).
A crossed module is equivalent to a category internal to Grp.
A Baez-Crans 2-vector space is a category internal to Vect.
A 2-group is an internal category in Grp and so has an internal nerve, which is a simplicial object in Grp, that is a simplicial group. If the 2-group corresponds to a crossed module, , then the simplicial group nerve of has Moore complex having in dimension 0, and in dimension 1, with the trivial group in all other dimensions. The only possible non-trivial boundary map from dimension 1 to dimension 0 is then the boundary of the crossed module.
If the ambient (finitely complete) category is a cartesian closed category, then the category of categories internal to is also cartesian closed. This was proved twice by Charles and Andrée (under her maiden name Bastiani) Ehresmann using generalised sketches, or may be proven directly as follows (see also Johnstone, remark after B2.3.15):
Let be a finitely complete cartesian closed category. Then the category of internal categories in is also finitely complete and cartesian closed.
First suppose is finitely complete. Then, since is the category of models for a limit sketch in , it follows that is also finitely complete.
Now suppose that is finitely complete and cartesian closed. Let denote the category of nonempty ordinals up to and including the ordinal with 4 elements. We have a full and faithful embedding
where the codomain category is cartesian closed. Indeed, the exponential of two objects , in may be computed as an -enriched end
when evaluated at , as is easily checked (see for instance here); note that this end is a finite limit diagram since is finite.
If , are internal categories in , seen as functors , the exponential defines the exponential in . To see this, it suffices to check that , as defined by the end formula above, is a category , i.e., is in the essential image of the nerve functor. For in that case, we have natural isomorphisms
whence satisfies the universal property required of an exponential.
Objects in the essential image of the nerve are characterized as functors which take intervalic joins in to pullbacks in , as given precisely by the Segal conditions. The remainder of the proof is then finished by the following lemma.
If satisfies the Segal conditions and is any functor, then also satisfies the Segal conditions.
For any we have the formula
Since the enriched end and the internal hom-functor both preserve pullbacks, we are reduced to checking that
as a functor in the argument (for each fixed ).
Note that the displayed statement is a proposition in the language of finitely complete categories (i.e., in finitary essentially algebraic logic). Since hom-functors jointly preserve and reflect the validity of such propositions, it suffices to prove it for the case where . But this is classical elementary category theory; it says precisely that if is a small (ordinary) category, then the usual functor categories , are equivalently described by exponentials of (truncated) simplicial sets. This completes the proof.
If the ambient category is a topos, then with the right kind of notion of internal functor, the internal groupoids form the corresponding (2,1)-topos of groupoid-valued stacks and the internal categories form the corresponding 2-topos of category-valued stacks/2-sheaves.
For the precise statement see at 2-topos – In terms of internal categories
See internalization versus enrichment.
The general definition of internal categories seems to have first been formulated in:
following the general principle of internalization formulated in
The concept of topological groupoids and Lie groupoids goes back to
and their understanding as categories internal to TopologicalSpaces and to SmoothManifolds is often attributed to
but it seems that the definition is not actually contained in there, certainly not in its simple and widely understood form due to Grothendieck 61.
The observation that (internal) categories are monads in the bicategory of spans:
Marta Bunge, Categories of set valued functors, PhD thesis, University of Pennsylvania (1966) [pdf]
Jean Bénabou, §5.4.3 in: Introduction to Bicategories, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 47 Springer (1967) 1-77 [doi:10.1007/BFb0074299]
Jean Celeyrette, Catégories internes et fibrations & Cohomologie de Gel’fand-Fuks, PhD thesis, Paris (1975) [pdf]
On category-valued stacks (2-sheaves) as internal categories in a sheaf topos, and on weak equivalences of internal categories:
Marta Bunge, Robert Paré, Stacks and equivalence of indexed categories, Cahiers de Top. et Géom. Diff. Catég 20 4 (1979) 373-399 [numdam:CTGDC_1979__20_4_373_0]
Marta Bunge, Stack completions and Morita equivalence for categories in a topos, Cahiers de Top. et Géom. Diff. Catég 20 4, (1979) 401-436 [numdam, MR558106]
Establishing the canonical model structure for internal categories in a Grothendieck topos:
and in the further generality of finitely complete categories:
Review of the basics of internal categories:
The notion of internal profunctors between internal categories (without recalling their definition) is due to:
An early textbook account with explicit definitions of internal categories, internal functors and internal profunctors:
Further textbook accounts:
Saunders MacLane, §XII.1 of: Categories for the Working Mathematician, Graduate Texts in Mathematics 5 Springer (second ed. 1997) [doi:10.1007/978-1-4757-4721-8]
Francis Borceux, Chapter 8 in Vol 1, Basic Category Theory , of: Handbook of Categorical Algebra, Cambridge University Press (1994) (doi:10.1017/CBO9780511525858)
Bart Jacobs, Chapter 7 in: Categorical Logic and Type Theory, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics 141, Elsevier (1998) [ISBN:978-0-444-50170-7, pdf]
and with emphasis on an ambient topos theory:
Peter Johnstone, Section B2.3 in: Vol. 1 of: Sketches of an Elephant – A Topos Theory Compendium, Oxford University Press (2002)(ISBN:9780198534259)
Saunders MacLane, Ieke Moerdijk, section V.7 of: Sheaves in Geometry and Logic (1992)
Survey and introduction with an eye towards Lie theory:
Jean Pradines, In Ehresmann‘s footsteps: from Group Geometries to Groupoid Geometries, Banach Center Publications, vol. 76, Warsawa 2007, 87-157 (arXiv:0711.1608, doi:10.4064/bc76-0-5)
John Baez, Alissa Crans, Higher-Dimensional Algebra VI: Lie 2-Algebras
The original proofs that the category of internal categories is cartesian closed when the ambient category is finitely complete and cartesian closed are in
Andrée Bastiani, Charles Ehresmann, Catégories de foncteurs structurés, Cahiers de Topologie et Géométrie Différentielle Catégoriques, 11 no. 3 (1969), p. 329-384 (numdam:CTGDC_1969__11_3_329_0)
Andrée Bastiani, Charles Ehresmann, Categories of sketched structures, Cahiers de Topologie et Géométrie Différentielle Catégoriques, 13 no. 2 (1972), p. 104-214 (Numdam)
See also:
Discussion in terms of monads in spans:
Discussion of the canonical model structure on categories of internal categories:
Discussion of localization and anafunctors between internal categories:
An old discussion on variants of internal categories, crossed modules and 2-groups is archived here.
A good general reference:
Last revised on October 1, 2024 at 21:49:14. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.