model category, model -category
Definitions
Morphisms
Universal constructions
Refinements
Producing new model structures
Presentation of -categories
Model structures
for -groupoids
on chain complexes/model structure on cosimplicial abelian groups
related by the Dold-Kan correspondence
for equivariant -groupoids
for rational -groupoids
for rational equivariant -groupoids
for -groupoids
for -groups
for -algebras
general -algebras
specific -algebras
for stable/spectrum objects
for -categories
for stable -categories
for -operads
for -categories
for -sheaves / -stacks
What is known as left Bousfield localization of model categories (Hirschhorn (2002), §3.3 following Bousfield (1975)) is a special case of localization of model categories corresponding to reflective localization, namely it is a Quillen reflection inducing a reflective sub--category inclusion in the associated -categories.
Recall that the reflective localization of a category at a set of morphisms can be presented as the category of fractions of with respect to the class of -local equivalences. In complete analogy to this, the left Bousfield localization of a model category (and, more generally, of a relative category ) at a set of morphisms can be presented as the same underlying category of equipped with the larger class of weak equivalences, called the -local morphisms.
Here the process of enlarging the class of weak equivalences can be seen as the homotopy coherent analogue of the classical category of fractions.
The historically original example is the Bousfield localization of spectra [Bousfield (1975)], but the notion is much more general, as explained above.
The existence of Bousfield localizations for cellular model categories was established in Hirschhorn (2002), Ch. 4 and for combinatorial model categories in Barwick (2010), Thm. 4.7 (based on Smith’s theorem) with discussion for the special case of simplicial model categories also in Lurie (2009), around A.3.7.3.
The left localization of a model category with respect to a class of morphisms in is the initial object (if it exists) in the following category:
The objects are left Quillen functors whose left derived functor sends elements of to weak equivalences in
the morphisms are commutative triangles of left Quillen functors.
This definition immediately implies that left localizations, if they exist, are unique up to a unique isomorphism.
The adjective “left” in Def. refers to the fact that the localization functor is implemented as the left derived functor of , in complete analogy to how the localization functor for a reflective localization is a left adjoint functor.
Right localizations are defined analogously and generalize coreflective localizations.
Let be a model category with a class of morphisms .
We want to characterize objects in that “see elements of as weak equivalences”.
In an ordinary category , by the Yoneda lemma a morphism is an isomorphism precisely if for all objects the morphism
is an isomorphism (of sets, i.e., a bijection).
So we can “test isomorphism by homming them into objects”.
More generally, recall the following facts about reflective localizations. If is a category and is a class of morphisms in , then an -local object is an object such that for every in , the map is an isomorphism. An -local equivalence is a morphism such that for every -local object , the map is an isomorphism. The reflective localization of at (if it exists) is defined as an initial object in the category whose objects are left adjoint functors that send elements of to isomorphisms in , and morphisms are commutative triangles of left adjoint functors. The functor from the full subcategory of -local objects in into the category of fractions of with respect to -local equivalences is an equivalence of categories. Thus, both domain and codomain of the above functor are models for the reflective localization of at .
The following definitions offer a completely analogous picture for model categories.
(-local objects and -local weak equivalences) We say that
an object is an -local object if for all in the morphism
is a weak equivalence of simplicial sets, where denotes the homotopy function complex, implemented, for example, as the hammock localization;
conversely, say that a map is an -local weak equivalence if for all -local objects the morphism is a weak equivalence of simplicial sets.
We write for the collection of -local weak equivalences.
For every weak equivalence between cofibrant objects and every fibrant object in a simplicial model category the map
is a weak equivalence of simplicial sets. This is described in detail at enriched homs from cofibrants to fibrants.
Every ordinary weak equivalence is also -local weak equivalence.
(left Bousfield localization)
The left Bousfield localization of a model category at a class of morphisms is, if it exists, the new model category structure on with
cofibrations are the same as before, ;
weak equivalences are -local equivalences.
Again, the adjective “left” refers to the fact that the localization is implemented by the left derived functor, generalizing reflective localizations.
Right Bousfield localizations are defined analogously and generalize coreflective localizations.
Any left Bousfield localization of at is also a left localization of at . Likewise for right localizations.
In practice, left localizations are always constructed as left Bousfield localizations. Therefore, both notions are used interchangeably.
A left Bousfield localization of a model category is another model category structure on the same underlying category with the same cofibrations,
but more weak equivalences
While that’s a very simple definition, it turns out that something interesting happens to the fibrations when we keep the cofibrations fixed and increase the weak equivalences.
It follows directly that
has as fibrations a sub-class of the fibrations of
has the same acyclic fibrations as
on the underlying categories
the identity functor preserves cofibrations and weak equivalences
the identity functor preserves fibrations and acyclic fibrations
so that this pair of functors is a Quillen adjunction
and a very special one: With the full subcategory on fibrant-cofibrant objects, under left Bousfield localization the fibrant-cofibrant objects of are a subcollection of those of , so that we have the full subcategory
Moreover, as we shall see, every object in is weakly equivalent in to one in : it reflects into .
Bousfield localization is a model category version of reflection onto local objects, in the sense discussed at reflective localization.
Indeed, the Quillen adjunction given by a left Bousfield localization under passage to the sub-category of fibrant-cofibrant objects becomes the inclusion of a reflective (∞,1)-subcategory
hence of a localization of an (∞,1)-category.
Such a localization is determined by the collection of local weak equivalences in , and alternatively by the collection of -local objects in . Indeed, is the full -subcategory on the cofibrant and fibrant and -local objects of .
Assume that the left Bousfield localization of a given model category at a class of morphisms in exists. Then it has the following properties.
The fibrant objects in are precisely the fibrant objects in that are -local.
To see this, we modify, if necessary, the set in a convenient way without changing the class of -local weak equivalences that it defines.
Lemma We may add to any set of -local cofibrations without changing the collection of -local objects and hence without changing the collection of -local weak equivalences themselves. In particular, we may add to without changing
all generating acyclic cofibrations of , i.e. ;
for every original morphism in and for every also the canonical morphism
Proof of the Lemma
We discuss why these morphisms of the latter type are indeed -local cofibrations with cofibrant domain:
to see that is indeed a cofibration notice that for every commuting diagram
we get as components of the top morphism the left square of
and similarly the components of the bottom morphism consitute a morphism which by the commutativity of the original square is a lift of the outer diagram here. The top left triangle of this lift in turn gives a square
So this last diagram has a lift and this is adjunct to the lift of the original lifting problem that we are looking for.
Therefore is indeed a cofibration.
Notice that in these arguments we made use of
the powering and copowering of the simplicially enriched category over SSet
and of the Quillen bifunctor property of the copowering which ensures that the fibrations and cofibrations are as indicated.
Next, again using the Quillen bifunctor property of the tensoring of over SSet we find that with cofibrant in and being cofibrant in SSet it follows that is cofibrant; similarly for the other cases. The coproduct of two cofibrant objects is cofibrant because cofibrations are preserved under pushout. Therefore is indeed a cofibrant domain of our cofibration.
With being a cofibration, we can check -locality by homming into fibrant -local objects and checking if that produces an acyclic Kan fibration.
So let be a fibrant and -local object of . Homming the defining pushout diagram for into produces the pullback diagram
in SSet. Here the top and the lowest morphisms are weak equivalences by the fact that is an acyclic Kan fibration by the characterization of -local cofibrations and the fact that SSet is an SSet-enriched model category. Similarly for the fibration on the left, which implies by right properness of SSet that the bottom horizontal morphism is a weak equivalence, which finally implies by 2-out-of-3 that the morphism in question is a weak equivalence.
end of the proof of the lemma
This shows that we can assume that contain the generating acyclic cofibrations and the morphism called .
As usual, we say that given a set of morphisms and an object that has the extension property with respect to if every diagram
has a lift.
We claim now that the the objects of that have the extension property with respect to our set are precisely the fibrant and -local objects. The argument proceeds along the same lines as the proof of the above lemma.
In one direction, if that has the extension property with respect to it has it in particular with respect to the generating acyclic cofibrations and hence is fibrant, and it, in particular, has the extension property with respect to . Observe that by the pushout definition of a morphism
consists of two component maps and such that
and in terms of this a lift
consists of a lift
Since are the generating acylic fibrations in the standard model structure on simplicial sets, this shows the extension property of with respect to all means that all are acyclic Kan fibrations.
Conversely, if is fibrant and -local, then for all in the map in is an acyclic Kan fibration hence in particular its underlying map of sets is a surjection, so has the extension property.
Now every fibrant object in has the extension property with respect to hence in particular with respect to , so is -local and fibrant in .
Conversely, if it is -local and fibrant in ; then, as mentioned before, for all the map is an acyclic Kan fibration in SSet so that in particular is a surjection, which means that has the extension property with respect to all and is hence fibrant in .
If is a small set, we may apply the small object argument to . If we apply it to factor all morphisms to the terminal object we obtain a functorial factorization componentwise of the form
We had remarked already in the previous argument that objects with the extension property relative to , i.e. objects whose morphism to the terminal object is in , are fibrant as well as -local in .
Therefore is in particular a fibrant approximation functor in and is the weak equivalence
in relating an object to its fibrant approximation.
More precisely:
Let
be a Quillen adjunction which exhibits a left Bousfield localization of model categories, and assume that admits functorial factorization (for instance if is a combinatorial model category, whence is, then via the small object argument), hence in particular a fibrant replacement natural transformation
Then the derived adjunction unit, i.e. the adjunction unit of adjoint pair of the derived functors on the homotopy category (as discussed there)
is isomorphic to the image of the fibrant replacement morphism in :
where is the localization functor (as discussed at homotopy category of a model category).
First consider the general prescription (from homotopy category of a model category) of computing the right (left) derived functors by applying the Quillen functors to fibrant (cofibrant) replacements, where we apply the fibrant replacement functorially also to the non-cofibrantly replaced object:
Let
be a general Quillen adjunction betwen model categories which admit functorial factorization.
Let be any object. First consider a cofibrant replacement
Then apply to this
Then apply fibrant replacement functorially
Then apply
Finally, precompose with the ordinary adjunction unit. The derived adjunction unit is now modeled by the top composite morphism in the following diagram:
Now in the special case that is a left Bousfield localization of model categories, then as plain categories and as plain functors and are trivial and so in this special case the derived adjunction unit is modeled simply by the top morphism in the following diagram
But now since the vertical morphisms are weak equivalences, this means that already the fibrant replacement is isomorphic, in the homotopy category, to the derived adjunction unit, i.e. applying the localization to the above diagram in yields the diagram
The -local weak equivalences between -local fibrant objects are precisely the original weak equivalences between these objects.
Consider the full subcategory of the homotopy category of on the -local objects. The image of an -local weak equivalence in there satisfies for every object in there that is an isomorphism. By the Yoneda lemma this implies that is an isomorphism in . Since that is a full subcategory, it follows that is also an isomorphism in . But that means precisely that it is a weak equivalence in .
It follows that also the fibrations between local objects remain the same:
Consider a left Bousfield localization with functorial factorization (e.g. of a combinatorial model category, via the small object argument).
Then if are local objects, a morphism between them is a fibration with respect to the local model structure precisely already if it is a fibration with respect to the original model structure.
From remark we already know that , generally. Hence we need to show that if with and local, then .
So given a lifting problem of the form
we need to exhibit a lift. (In labeling the arrows we use throughout that .)
By assumption of functorial factorization we may factor this diagram as follows:
It follows that .
Consider next the further factorization of the middle vertical morphism as
Since it follows that we invoke prop. to conclude that the top middle morphism is not just in but indeed in , as shown. This means that we have lifting in the top right square. Moreover, we also evidently have lifting in the bottom left square.
Together, these lifts constitute the desired total lift.
We have considered two definitions of left Bousfield localization: in the first we just required that cofibrations are kept and weak equivalences are increased. In the second we more specifically took the weak equivalences to be -local weak equivalences.
We now show that every localization in the first sense is indeed of the second kind if we demand that both the original and the localized category are left proper, cofibrantly generated simplicial model categories.
In the context of left proper, cofibrantly generated simplicial model categories,
for a left Bousfield localization of (i.e. a structure with the same cofibrations as and more weak equivalences), there is a set such that
We show that choosing to be the set of generating acyclic cofibrations does the trick.
First, the cofibrations of and coincide. Moreover, the acyclic cofibrations of contain all the acyclic cofibrations of because
It remains to show that, conversely, every acyclic cofibration in is an acyclic cofibration in .
Choose a cofibrant replacement for and
Then by 2-out-of-3 and since the morphism is still an acyclic cofibration on . Again by 2-out-of-3 and since , it is sufficient to show that is an acyclic cofibration in .
To show that it is an acyclic cofibration in it suffices to show that for every fibrant object the morphism
is a trivial fibration. Either by assumption or by the characterization of S-local cofibrations this is the case if is -local and fibrant in . The first statement is one of the direct consequences of the definition of and the second follows because .
Let and be categories for which left Bousfield localization exists, and let
be a Quillen equivalence. Then for every small set there is an induced Quillen equivalence of left Bousfield localizations
This is due to Hirschhorn (2002).
If the left Bousfield localization exists, i.e. is indeed a model category with the above definitions of cofibrations and weak equivalences, then it is indeed a localization of a model category in that there is a left Quillen functor
(i.e. preserves cofibrations and trivial cofibrations and has a right adjoint)
such that the total left derived functor
takes the images of in to isomorphisms
and every other left Quillen functor with this property factors by a unique left Quillen functor through .
Moreover, the identity functor on the underlying category is a Quillen adjunction
(and is itself a localization functor).
The first part is theorem 3.3.19 in Hirschhorn (2002). The second part is prop 3.3.4, which follows directly from the following proposition.
We discuss the existence of left Bousfield localization in the context of combinatorial model categories [Barwick (2010), Prop. 2.2 (Thm. 2.11 in preprint)].
A similar existence result is available in the context of cellular model categories [Hirschhorn (2002)], but for the combinatorial case a somewhat better theory is available.
By the corollary to Dugger's theorem on presentations for combinatorial model categories we have that every combinatorial model category is Quillen equivalent to a left proper simplicial combinatorial model category.
Therefore there is little loss in assuming this extra structure, which the following statement of the theorem does.
If is a
then the left Bousfield localization does exist as a combinatorial model category.
Moreover, it satisfies the following conditions:
the fibrant objects of are precisely the -local objects of that are fibrant in ;
is itself a left proper model category;
is itself a simplicial model category.
(Without the assumption or conclusion of simplicial enrichment, this is Barwick (2010), Prop. 2.2 (Thm. 2.11 in preprint), see also Beke (2000), Thm. 1.7, Prop. 1.15 & 1.19).
A proof of this making use of Jeff Smith’s recognition theorem for combinatorial model categories appears as HTT, prop. A.3.7.3 and as theorem 2.11 in Bar07 and as theorem 4.7 in Bar.
We follow Bar for the proof that the assumptions of Smith’s recognition theorem are satisfied and follow HTT, prop. A.3.7.3 for the characterization of the fibrant objects. The details are spelled out in the following subsections.
The proof we give is self-contained, except that it builds on the following notions and facts.
A cardinal number is regular if it is not the cardinality of a union of sets of size .
A poset is a -directed set if all subsets of cardinality have a common upper bound. A -directed colimit is a colimit over a functor .
An object in a category is a -compact object if commutes with all -directed colimits. For every -compact object is also -compact.
This means that a morphism from a -compact object into an object that is a -directed colimit over component objects always lifts to one of these component objects.
An object is a small object if it is -compact for some .
A locally small but possibly non-small category is an accessible category if it has a small sub-set of generating -compact objects such that every other object is a -directed colimit over such generators.
If such a category has all small colimits, it is called a locally presentable category.
In particular, in a locally presentable category the small object argument for factoring of morphisms applies with respect to every set of morphisms.
A combinatorial model category is a locally presentable category that is equipped with a cofibrantly generated model category structure. So in particular there is a set of generating (acyclic) cofibrations that map between small objects.
Smith’s recognition theorem says that a locally presentable category has a combinatorial model category structure already if it has weak equivalences and generating cofibrations satisfying a simple condition and if weak equivalences form an accessible subcategory of the arrow category. This means that only two thirds of the data for a generic combinatorial model category needs to be checked and greatly facilitates checking model category structures.
Dugger’s theorem implies that every combinatorial model category is Quillen equivalent to a left proper simplicial combinatorial model category.
So we may assume without much restriction of generality that we are dealing with the localization of a left proper combinatorial simplicial model category.
Since the small object argument applies, a combinatorial model category has fibrant- and cofibrant-replacement functors (functorial factorization).
By the axioms of an enriched model category it follows that the functor
takes values in Kan complexes. This is called the derived hom space functor of : we think of as the ∞-groupoid of maps from to , homotopies of maps, homotopies of homotopies, etc.
An ordinary reflective subcategory is specified by the preimages of the isomorphisms under as the full subcategory on the -local objects : those such that are isomorphisms.
The analogous statement in the context of model categories uses the derived hom space functor instead: given a collection an object is called an -local object if are weak equivalences.
Similarly, the collection of morphisms such that for all -local objects is a weak equivalence is called the collection of -local weak equivalences.
A lemma by Lurie says that for a cofibration and fibrant, is -local precisely if is an acyclic Kan fibration. This helps identifying the -local fibrant objects.
In an ordinary category, a limit diagram is one such that applying to it produces a limit diagram in Set, for all objects . Similarly a colimit diagram is one sent to Set-limits under all .
In a model category, this has an analog with respect to the derived hom space functor . A homotopy limit diagram is one sent by all to a homotopy limit (…). Similarly for homotopy colimits.
Sometimes ordinary (co)limits in a model category are already also homotopy colimits:
an observation by Barwick shows that in a left proper simplicial model category ordinary pushouts along cofibrations are already homotopy colimits.
an observation by Dugger shows that transfinite composition colimits of length in a combinatorial model category are automatically homotopy colimits for sufficiently large .
Since these are the two operations under which is closed, this facilitates finding this closure given that by the above the elements of are characterized by their images under for -local .
The following proof uses the small object argument several times. In particular, at one point it is applied relative to the collection of morphisms at which we localize. It is at this point that we need that assumption that is indeed a (small) set, and not a proper class.
For the small object argument itself, this requirement comes from the fact that it involves colimits indexed by . These won’t in general exist if is not a set.
The collection of -local weak equivalences , however, won’t be a small set in general even if is. But for Smith’s recognition theorem to apply we need to check that the full subcategory of on is, while not small, accessible.
To establish this we need two properties of accessible categories: the inverse image of an accessible subcategory under a functor is accessible, and the collections of fibrations, weak equivalences and acyclic fibrations in a combinatorial model category are accessible.
Beginning of the proof of the existence of the left Bousfield localization of a left proper combinatorial simplicial model category at a set of morphisms.
Using Smith’s recognition theorem, for establishing the combinatorial model category structure, it is sufficient to
exhibit a set of cofibrations of such that and such that is closed under pushout and transfinite composition.
check that the weak equivalences form an accessibly embedded accessible subcategory.
For the first item choose with any set of generating cofibrations of , that exists by assumption on . Then .
It remains to demonstrate closure of under pushout and transfinite composition.
One elegant way to see this, following Bar, is to notice that the relevant ordinary colimits all happen to be homotopy colimits:
all pushouts along cofibrations in a left proper model category are homotopy pushouts (details are here);
all transfinite composition colimits in a combinatorial model category are homotopy colimits (details are here)
By their definition in terms of the derived hom space functor, -local weak equivalences in are preserved under homotopy colimits:
for an -local morphism – a morphism in – and for
a homotopy pushout diagram, we have (by the universal property of homotopy limits) for every object – in particular for every every -local object – a homotopy pullback
of -groupoids. where the bottom morphism is a weak equivalence by assumption of -locality of and . But then also the top horizontal morphism is a weak equivalence for all -local and therefore is in .
Similarly for transfinite composition colimits.
Therefore, indeed, is closed under pushouts and transfinite composition.
For the Smith recognition theorem to apply we still have to check that the -local weak equivalences span an accessible full subcategory of the arrow category of .
By the general properties of accessible categories for that it is sufficient to exhibit as the inverse image of under functor of the accessible category spanned by ordinary weak equivalences in .
That functor we take to be the -local fibrant replacement functor from above
By one of the above propositions, -local weak equivalence between -local objects are precisely the ordinary weak equivalences. This means that the inverse image under of the weak equivalences in are all -local weak equivalences
Therefore this is an accessible category.
End of the proof of the existence of the left Bousfield localization of a left proper combinatorial simplicial model category at a set of morphisms.
Every combinatorial localization of is already of the form for a set of just cofibrations.
If one assumes large cardinal axioms then the existence of Bousfield localization follows much more generally.
Vopěnka's principle implies the statement:
Let be a left proper combinatorial model category and a class of morphisms. Then the left Bousfield localization exists.
This is theorem 2.3 in (RosickyTholen).
The above statement is generalized to the context of enriched model category theory by the following result:
Let
a small set
(all with respect to a fixed Grothendieck universe).
Then the left enriched Bousfield localization does exist and is left proper and tractable.
This is (Barwick 2007a, theorem 4.46).
The following model categories are left proper cellular/combinatorial, so that the above theorem applies and for every set the Bousfield localization does exist.
Top with its standard model structure on topological spaces;
SSet with its standard model structure on simplicial sets;
the category of symmetric spectra in a pointed left-proper cellular model category
and so on…
If is a left proper (simplicial) cellular model category, then so is
the functor category for any (simplicial) small category (using the global model structure on functors);
the over category for any object .
The Bousfield-Friedlander theorem gives Bousfield localizations at the derived functor-version of idempotent monads.
See there for more examples of this general construction.
see Bousfield localization of spectra
Left Bousfield localization produces the local model structure on homotopical presheaves. For instance the local model structure on simplicial presheaves.
As described at presentable (∞,1)-category, an (∞,1)-category is presentable precisely if, as an simplicially enriched category, it arises as the full subcategory of fibrant-cofibrant objects of a combinatorial simplicial model category.
The proof of this proceeds via Bousfield localization, and effectively exhibits Bousfield localization as the procedure that models localization of an (∞,1)-category when -categories are modeled by model categories.
For notice that
a presentable -category is one arising as the localization
every (∞,1)-category of (∞,1)-presheaves arises as the subcategory of fibrant-cofibrant objects of the global model structure on simplicial presheaves;
in terms of the simplicial model category the prescription for localization as an (∞,1)-category and passing to the subcategory of fibrant-cofibrant objects of the Bousfield localization is literally the same: in both cases one passes to the full subcategory on the -local objects.
Moreover, by Dugger’s theorem on combinatorial model categories every combinatorial simplicial model category arises this way.
This is the argument of HTT, prop A.3.7.6.
This gives a good conceptual interpretation of Bousfield localization, since the localization of an (∞,1)-category is nothing but an adjunction
that exhibits as a reflective (∞,1)-subcategory of .
So we find the diagram
Localization of -presheaf categories
Here denotes passing to the full simplicially enriched subcategory on the fibrant-cofibrant objects, regarding that as an (∞,1)-category. (If one wants to regard that as a quasi-category, then also involves taking the homotopy coherent nerve of this simplicially enriched category.)
There is also a notion of Bousfield localization of triangulated categories.
Under suitable conditions it should be true that for a model category whose homotopy category is a triangulated category the homotopy category of a left Bousfield localization of is the left Bousfield localization of . See this answer on MO.
The original article:
Detailed discussion (including existence results for left proper cellular model categories):
Existence results for (plain an enriched) combinatorial model categories:
see also
and specifically for combinatorial simplicial model categories:
The relation to localization of an (infinity,1)-category is also in Higher Topos Theory, for the time being see discussion at models for ∞-stack (∞,1)-toposes.
On right Bousfield localization:
The relation to Vopěnka's principle:
Bousfield localization specifically for stable model categories (such as model structures on spectra):
Comprehensive review:
On monoidal Bousfield localization of monoidal model categories:
Sergey Gorchinskiy, Vladimir Guletskii, Lemma 28 in: Symmetric powers in abstract homotopy categories, Adv. Math. 292 (2016) 707-754 [arXiv:0907.0730, doi:10.1016/j.aim.2016.01.011]
David White, Monoidal Bousfield Localizations and Algebras over Operads, PhD thesis (2014), published in Equivariant Topology and Derived Algebra: A conference in honor of John Greenlees’ 60th birthday, Cambridge University Press (2021) 179-239 [doi:10.1017/9781108942874.007, digitalcollections:ir-2263, arXiv:1404.5197]
Tyler Lawson, Prop. 12.18 in: An introduction to Bousfield localization, in: Stable categories and structured ring spectra, MSRI Book Series, Cambridge University Press (2022) [arXiv:2002.03888]
Luca Pol, Jordan Williamson, The Left Localization Principle, completions, and cofree -spectra, J. Pure Appl. Algebra 224 11 (2020) 106408 [arXiv:1910.01410, doi:10.1016/j.jpaa.2020.106408]
Last revised on December 28, 2023 at 21:44:42. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.