Background
Basic concepts
equivalences in/of -categories
Universal constructions
Local presentation
Theorems
Extra stuff, structure, properties
Models
homotopy theory, (∞,1)-category theory, homotopy type theory
flavors: stable, equivariant, rational, p-adic, proper, geometric, cohesive, directed…
models: topological, simplicial, localic, …
see also algebraic topology
Introductions
Definitions
Paths and cylinders
Homotopy groups
Basic facts
Theorems
An -truncated ∞-groupoid is an n-groupoid.
An -truncated topological space is a homotopy n-type: all homotopy groups above degree are trivial.
An -truncated object in a general (∞,1)-category is an object such that all hom-∞-groupoids into it are -truncated.
If an object in an (∞,1)-topos is -truncated for any (possibly large) , then it is -truncated precisely if all its categorical homotopy groups above degree are trivial.
The complementary notion of -truncated object is that of an n-connected object of an (∞,1)-category.
(-truncated -groupoid)
An ∞-groupoid is -truncated for if it is an n-groupoid:
Precisely: in the model of ∞-groupoids given by Kan complexes is -truncated if the simplicial homotopy groups are trivial for all and all .
It makes sense for the following to adopt the convention that is called.
-truncated if it is empty or contractible – this is a (-1)-groupoid.
-truncated if it is non-empty and contractible – this is a (-2)-groupoid.
(following HTT, p. 6).
To generalize this, let now be an arbitrary (∞,1)-category. For objects in write ∞Grpd for the (∞,1)-categorical hom-space (if is given as a simplicially enriched category then this is just the SSet-hom-object which is guaranteed to be a Kan complex).
Using this, it is useful to reformulate the above as follows slightly:
An ∞-groupoid is -truncated precisely when for all ∞-groupoids the hom--groupoid is -truncated.
In other category-theoretic terms this says that (∞,k)-transformation between and , whose components are k-morphisms in , cannot be nontrivial for if there are no nontrivial k-morphisms with in .
Using this fact we can transport the notion of -truncation to any (∞,1)-category by testing it on hom--groupoids:
(-truncated object in an -category)
Given an (∞,1)-category , an object is called -truncated, for , if for all objects the hom-∞-groupoid is -truncated according to Def. .
This is HTT, def. 5.5.6.1.
Some terminology:
A 0-truncated object is also called discrete. Notice that this is categorically discrete as in discrete category, not discrete in the sense of discrete topological space. An object in an (∞,1)-topos is discrete in this sense if, regarded as an ∞-groupoid with extra structure, it has only trivial morphisms.
By the above convention on (-2)-truncated -groupoids, it is only the terminal objects of that are (-2)-truncated.
Similarly, the (-1)-truncated objects are the subterminal objects.
(-truncated morphism in an -category)
A morphism of ∞-groupoids is -truncated if all of its homotopy fibers are -truncated by def. .
A morphism in an (∞,1)-category is -truncated if for all the postcomposition morphism
is -truncated in ∞Grpd.
This is HTT, def. 5.5.6.8.
By the characterization of homotopy fiber of functor categories this is equivalent to saying that is -truncated when it is so regarded as an object of the over (∞,1)-category . (See also HTT, rem. 5.5.6.12.)
Unwinding the definitions and applying the long exact sequence of homotopy groups, we have:
For , a morphism of ∞-groupoids is -truncated iff, for every point , we have is a monomorphism and for every , is an isomorphism.
is -trunacated iff it is a weak homotopy equivalence.
At least if the ambient (∞,1)-category is even an ∞-stack (∞,1)-topos there is an alternative, more intrinsic, characterization of -truncation in terms of categorical homotopy groups in an (∞,1)-topos:
Suppose that an object in an ∞-stack (∞,1)-topos is -truncated for some (possibly very large).
Then for any this is -truncated precisely if all the categorical homotopy groups above degree are trivial.
This is HTT, prop 6.5.1.7.
Notice that this expected statement does require the assumption that is -truncated for some . Without any a priori truncation assumption on , there is no comparable statement about the relation to categorical homotopy groups. See HTT, remark 6.5.1.8.
In an -category with finite limits, a morphism is -truncated (for ) precisely if the diagonal morphism is -truncated.
This is HTT, lemma 5.5.6.15.
By definition is -truncated if for each object we have that is -truncated in ∞Grpd. Since the hom-functors preserve (∞,1)-limits, we have in particular that in is -truncated if is -truncated for all in ∞Grpd. Therefore it is sufficient to prove the statement for morphisms in ∞Grpd.
So let now be a morphism of ∞-groupoids. We may find a fibration between Kan complexes in sSet that models in the standard model structure on simplicial sets, and by the standard rules for homotopy pullbacks it follows that the object in -Grpd is then modeled by the ordinary pullback in sSet. And the homotopy fibers of over are then given by the ordinary fibers of in .
This way, the statement is reduced to the following fact: a Kan complex is -truncated precisely if the homotopy fibers of are -truncated.
We now write for for simplicity. To see the last statement, let and compute the homotopy pullback
as usual by replacing the right vertical morphism with the fibration and then forming the ordinary pullback. This shows that is equivalent to the space of paths in from to . (Use that gluing of path space objects at endpoints of paths produces a new path space; see, for instance, section 4 of BrownAHT).
If is connected, then choosing any path gives an isomorphism from the homotopy groups of to those of the loop space . These latter are indeed those of , shifted down in degree by one (as described, for instance, at fiber sequence).
If is not connected, we can easily reduce to the case that it is.
For an -category and , the full sub-(∞,1)-category is stable under all -limits in .
This is HTT, prop. 5.5.6.5.
Let be an (∞,1)-topos. For all the class of -truncated morphisms in forms the right class in a orthogonal factorization system in an (∞,1)-category. The left class is that of n-connected morphisms in .
This appears as a remark in HTT, Example 5.2.8.16. A construction of the factorization in terms of a model category presentation is in (Rezk, prop. 8.5). See also n-connected/n-truncated factorization system.
There are model structures for homotopy n-types that presentable (∞,1)-category present the full sub-(∞,1)-categories of -truncated objects in some ambient -category. See there for more details.
Under mild conditions there is for each a universal way to send an arbitrary object to its -truncation . This is a general version of decategorification where n-morphisms are identified if they are connected by an invertible -morphism.
For an (∞,1)-category and in write for the full subcategory of on its -truncated objects.
So for instance for ∞Grpd we have .
If is an (∞,1)-category that is presentable then the canonical inclusion (∞,1)-functor
has an accessible left adjoint
This is HTT 5.5.6.18.
Indeed, as the notation suggests, is the essential image of under . The image of an object under this operation is the -truncation of .
So -truncated objects form a reflective sub-(∞,1)-category
For any small -category , , and truncation acts pointwise.
If is an -truncated ∞-presheaf, then is -truncated; thus takes values in .
Conversely, if takes values in , then the fact every presheaf is a colimit of representables implies is a limit of -truncated spaces and is thus -truncated.
Given this identification of the subcategory of -truncated objects, we can see that the truncation-inclusion adjunction between and induces an adjunction whose right adjoint is the inclusion
(left exact -functors preserve truncation)
A left exact -functor between -categories with finite -limits sends -truncated objects/morphisms to -truncated objects/morphisms.
This follows from the above recursive characterization of -truncated morphisms by the -truncation of their diagonal, which is preserved by the finite limit preserving .
A left exact presentable -functor between locally presentable (∞,1)-categories and commutes with truncation:
This is HTT, prop. 5.5.6.28.
By the above lemma, restricts to a functor on the truncations. So we need to show that the diagram
in (∞,1)Cat can be filled by a 2-cell. To see this, notice that the adjoint (∞,1)-functor of both composite morphisms exists (because that of exists by the adjoint (∞,1)-functor theorem and bcause adjoints of composites are composites of adjoints) and since the bottom morphism is just the restriction of the top morphism and the right adjoints of the vertical morphisms are full inclusions this adjoint diagram
evidently commutes since it just expresses this restriction.
If is an (∞,1)-topos, then truncation preserves finite products.
This appears as HTT, lemma 6.5.1.2.
First notice that the statement is true for ∞Grpd. For instance we can use the example In ∞Grpd and Top, model ∞-groupoids by Kan complexes and notice that then is given by the truncation functor . This is also a right adjoint and as such preserves in particular products in , which are -products in .
From that we deduce that the statement is true for any (∞,1)-category of (∞,1)-presheaves because all relevant operations there are objectwise those in .
So far, this shows even that on presheaf -toposes, all products (not necessarily finite) are preserved by truncation.
A general (∞,1)-topos is (by definition) a left exact reflective sub-(∞,1)-category of a presheaf -topos,
Let be the product of the objects in question taken in . By the above there, we have an equivalence
Now applying to this equivalence and using now that preserves the finite product, this gives an equivalence
in . The claim follows now with the above result that .
By the fact that the truncation functor is a left adjoint, one obtains canonical morphisms
as the adjunct of the identity on , and then by iteration also canonical morphisms
For any , the sequence
is the Postnikov tower in an (∞,1)-category of . See there for more details.
Discussion of -truncation of types in homotopy type theory via higher inductive types is in (Brunerie). This sends a type to an h-level -type. The -truncation in the context is forming the bracket type hProp.
See at n-truncation modality.
In an -topos there is a notion of categorical homotopy groups in an (∞,1)-topos. For the -topos ∞Grpd given by the model of Kan complexes this coincides with the notion of simplicial homotopy groups:
An object in the (∞,1)-topos ∞Grpd is -truncated precisely if its categorical homotopy groups vanish for all .
This simple relation between -truncation and categorical homotopy groups is almost, but not exactly, true in an arbitrary (∞,1)-topos.
Let be an (∞,1)-topos and an -truncated object.
Then
for we have for the categorical homotopy groups ;
if (for ) , then is in fact -truncated.
This implies
If is truncated at all (for any value), then it is -truncated precisely if all categorical homotopy groups vanish for .
Notice. If , on the other hand, is not truncated at all, then all its homotopy groups may be trivial, and may still not be equivalent to the terminal object. This means that Whitehead's theorem may fail in a general (∞,1)-topos for untruncated objects. It holds, however, in hypercomplete (∞,1)-toposes.
A morphism is
(-2)-truncated precisely if it is an equivalence;
(-1)-truncated precisely if it is a monomorphism.
For morphisms between 1-groupoids, the notion of -truncation for low reproduces standard concepts from ordinary category theory.
A functor between groupoids, is -truncated precisely when regarded as a morphism in ∞Grpd it is
for – an equivalence of categories;
for – a full and faithful functor;
for – a faithful functor.
Notice that being faithful means precisely that it induces a monomorphism on the first homotopy groups.
For any point and the corresponding homotopy fiber of , the long exact sequence of homotopy groups gives that is the kernel of an injective map
hence for all points in the essential image of . For not in the essential image we have . In either case, it follows that is 0-truncated.
By def. this is the defining condition for to be 0-truncated.
Let be a site and write for the (2,1)-topos of stacks/(2,1)-sheaves inside the (∞,1)-sheaf (∞,1)-topos of all ∞-stacks/(∞,1)-sheaves.
Write for the simplicial localization of groupoid valued presheaves in and write for the local projective model structure on simplicial presheaves that presents .
Let be a morphism of stacks that has a presentation by a degreewise faithful functor that, under the nerve, goes between fibrant simplicial presheaves.
Then is 0-truncated as a morphism in .
We need to check that for any -stack , the morphism is 0-truncated in ∞Grpd. We may choose a cofibrant model for in and by assumption that and is fibrant we have that the ordinary hom of simplicial presheaves is the correct derived hom space morphism. This is itself (the nerve of) a faithful functor, hence the statement follows with prop. .
An object in ∞Grpd is -truncated precisely if it is an n-groupoid. To some extent, this is so by definition. Equivalently, an object in Top is -truncated if it is (in the equivalence class of) a homotopy n-type.
So we have for a reflective sub-(∞,1)-category
If we model the (∞,1)-category ∞Grpd as the Kan complex-enriched category/fibrant simplicial category sSet of Kan complexes, then the truncation adjunction
is modeled by the simplicial coskeleton sSet-enriched adjunction
where is the subcategory of on those truncated simplicial sets that are truncations of Kan complexes, regarded as a Kan-complex-enriched category by the embedding via .
Notice that every Kan complex which is -truncated is homotopy equivalent to one in the image of , namely to , because by one of the properties of we have that the unit
induces isomorphisms on homotopy groups for .
This shows that is indeed a full sub-(∞,1)-category of on -truncated objects
Moreover, by the fact discussed at Simplicial and derived adjunctions at adjoint (∞,1)-functor we have that the sSet-enriched adjunction on indeed presents a pair of adjoint (∞,1)-functors on ∞Grpd. So indeed presents the left adjoint to the inclusion .
In ordinary category theory we have that a morphism is a monomorphism (as discussed there), precisely if its diagonal is an isomorphism. Embedded into (∞,1)-category, this becomes the special case of prop. for : a morphism is (-1)-truncated (hence a monomorphism in an (∞,1)-category), precisely if its diagonal is (-2)-truncated (hence an equivalence in an (∞,1)-category).
Let be an object that is -truncated. This means that is an -truncated morphism. So by prop. the diagonal on that object
is an -truncated morphism, and precisely if it is -truncated is -truncated.
In particular, the diagonal is a monomorphism in an (∞,1)-category, hence (-1)-truncated, precisely if is -truncated (an h-set).
-truncated morphism / n-connected morphism
homotopy level | n-truncation | homotopy theory | higher category theory | higher topos theory | homotopy type theory |
---|---|---|---|---|---|
h-level 0 | (-2)-truncated | contractible space | (-2)-groupoid | true/unit type/contractible type | |
h-level 1 | (-1)-truncated | contractible-if-inhabited | (-1)-groupoid/truth value | (0,1)-sheaf/ideal | mere proposition/h-proposition |
h-level 2 | 0-truncated | homotopy 0-type | 0-groupoid/set | sheaf | h-set |
h-level 3 | 1-truncated | homotopy 1-type | 1-groupoid/groupoid | (2,1)-sheaf/stack | h-groupoid |
h-level 4 | 2-truncated | homotopy 2-type | 2-groupoid | (3,1)-sheaf/2-stack | h-2-groupoid |
h-level 5 | 3-truncated | homotopy 3-type | 3-groupoid | (4,1)-sheaf/3-stack | h-3-groupoid |
h-level | -truncated | homotopy n-type | n-groupoid | (n+1,1)-sheaf/n-stack | h--groupoid |
h-level | untruncated | homotopy type | ∞-groupoid | (∞,1)-sheaf/∞-stack | h--groupoid |
Discussion in -category:
Discussion of categorical homotopy groups in an (∞,1)-topos is in section 6.5.1 there.
Discussion in terms of model category presentations:
A classical article that amplifies the expression of Postnikov towers in sSet (hence in ) in terms of coskeleta:
Discussion in the context of modal homotopy type theory:
Univalent Foundations Project, section 7.6 of Homotopy Type Theory – Univalent Foundations of Mathematics
Guillaume Brunerie, Truncations and truncated higher inductive types (web)
More discussion of the internal perspective:
Discussion of homotopy -types/-truncated objects in homotopy type theory:
Univalent Foundations Project, §7 of: Homotopy Type Theory – Univalent Foundations of Mathematics (2013) [web, pdf]
Nicolai Kraus, Truncation levels in Homotopy Type Theory, Nottingham (2015) [pdf, eprints:28986]
Felix Cherubini, Egbert Rijke, Thm. 3.10 of: Modal Descent, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science , 31 4 (2021) 363-391 [doi:10.1017/S0960129520000201, arXiv:2003.09713]
Last revised on June 25, 2024 at 07:42:40. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.