With braiding
With duals for objects
category with duals (list of them)
dualizable object (what they have)
ribbon category, a.k.a. tortile category
With duals for morphisms
monoidal dagger-category?
With traces
Closed structure
Special sorts of products
Semisimplicity
Morphisms
Internal monoids
Examples
Theorems
In higher category theory
In category theory, the Chu construction [Chu 1979; Barr 1991, 1996] is a method for constructing a star-autonomous category from a closed symmetric monoidal category.
Early discussion of application of the Chu construction as categorical semantics for linear logic is due to Barr 1991 and, motivated [Pratt 1992] by categorical semantics of quantum logic in star-autonomous categories, due to Pratt 1993, 1999.
In outline, given a closed symmetric monoidal category with pullbacks and an object of , there is a star-autonomous category and a strong symmetric monoidal functor
which realizes as a coreflective subcategory of . Being star-autonomous, is self-dual, in that its opposite category also embeds as a full subcategory of , this time reflectively.
Many concrete dualities in mathematics can be seen as embedded in a larger ambient self-duality on a Chu construction. This applies in particular to the category of Chu spaces, (see below).
Th Chu construction may be categorified to what might be called a 2-Chu construction, producing for example (see Shulman17). It also generalizes to a double Chu construction and to operations on multicategories and polycategories.
Let be a closed symmetric monoidal category and an object. The objects of are triples (called -valued pairings between and ), where and are objects of and is a morphism of . The special triple , where is an instance of the canonical isomorphism (the right unitor) for the monoidal unit , will play the role of dualizing object in .
The morphisms of ,
are pairs of morphisms , which are adjoints with respect to the pairings, that is, making the following diagram commute:
There is an evident self-duality functor
which takes an object to
where is an instance of the symmetry isomorphism, so that is the evident transpose. On morphisms, it takes a pair to ; note well that the directions of the arrows make the functor contravariant on .
Armed with just this much knowledge, and knowledge of how star-autonomous categories behave (as categorified versions of linear logic), the star-autonomous structure on can pretty much be deduced (or strongly guessed) by the diligent reader, and this is actually a very good exercise. One could sketch this as follows:
The monoidal unit of should be the dual of the dualizer, and so is where , the transpose of , is a canonical isomorphism for the unit .
The internal hom in should internalize the external hom, i.e., the set of maps from the monoidal unit to should be in natural bijection with the set of maps in .
This suggests the first component of the triple
should be the object of adjoint pairs of maps: given
define the first component as pullback:
where exponentials are used to denote internal homs in , is the result of currying to and exponentiating, and similarly for .
The pullback is paired with , i.e., there is a map
obtained by decurrying either leg of the pullback, so one defines (with fingers crossed) to be , and the pairing to be this map into .
With notation as above, this works out to
where the second component is a pullback, and the pairing omitted but obvious. The main thing to check is the presence of a canonical isomorphism
but this is left as an exercise.
Also one should check that if is the dualizing object, that , but this is straightforward.
There is a strong symmetric monoidal functor
taking to . (This does not take to the dualizing object in , unless of course the canonical map is an isomorphism.) This embedding admits a right adjoint
given by the obvious projection, that is also strong symmetric monoidal. The unit of the adjunction is an isomorphism, hence is a coreflective (full) subcategory of .
If is complete and cocomplete, then so is . The formula for colimits is the obvious expected one:
where is the decurrying of
and the formula for limits is obtained by dualizing the formula for colimits in .
We can also deduce the -autonomous structure of by constructing it directly as a star-polycategory and then observing that it is representable. This has the additional benefit of giving a universal property to the tensor product, as well as applying to more general inputs (and giving a result that may not be representable), and giving a convenient way to phrase the universal property of itself (see below).
Let be a (symmetric) polycategory in which every morphism has codomain arity 0 or 1 (a co-subunary polycategory). For instance, if is any symmetric multicategory and an object, we can obtain a co-subunary polycategory by defining . (In fact the construction can be generalized even further; see Shulman 18.)
The objects of are now pairings in the appropriate polycategorical sense. A morphism is a pair of morphisms and that are “adjoint” with respect to the pairings, in the sense that the following square commutes: More generally, we can directly make into a polycategory by taking the morphisms to be a suitable kind of multivariable adjunctions. For instance, a morphism consists of three morphisms
such that the following three composites are equal modulo symmetries:
Similarly, a morphism consists of three morphisms
such that three composite morphisms are equal. With a suitable extension to --ary morphisms we obtain a polycategory, and indeed a -polycategory: the dual of is .
It is then a straightforward exercise to check that if is closed, representable, has pullbacks, and a “counit” in the sense that , then is representable on both sides and hence a -autonomous category, where all the structure coincides with the previous definition.
While the Chu construction is worthy of exploration for many types of symmetric monoidal categories , a great deal of attention has been focused just on the particular case (or , where is the set of truth values, to be constructive), called the category of Chu spaces, and on relatives like where is a topos and its subobject classifier. The reason is that a great many concrete categories of interest are fully embedded in Chu spaces. Moreover, the 2-element set carries a panoply of ambimorphic (formerly, schizophrenic) object structures which induce concrete dualities between these categories, and all of these dualities are embedded in (i.e., are restrictions of) the one overarching duality that obtains on Chu spaces.
The way this works is invariably the same: if is a concrete category and is an object of over the 2-element set , then there is a functor
which is faithful by the notion of concrete category.
What is striking is that this functor is also full in many cases of interest. This is because the adjointness condition for a pair to be a Chu space morphism, together with faithfulness of , forces
to be a restriction of the preimage function – and then the mere additional fact that whenever is often enough to force to be (the underlying function of) a morphism of . All that is required is that there be sufficiently many morphisms to detect -structure on . Some examples follow:
As explained above, fully embeds in by .
For , taking to be Sierpinski space, we have for each topological space an identification . Then the adjointness condition on a morphism between the corresponding Chu spaces expresses precisely the continuity condition that the preimage takes opens of to opens of . Hence the functor is full.
For , the category of posets, take to be the partially ordered set of truth values. Here we have that for a partial order , is the set of upper sets (upward-closed subsets) of . Given a function between posets, the condition that the preimage of an upper set of is an upper set of is enough to force to be a poset map (consider ). It follows that the functor is full.
For , the category of sup-lattices (whose morphisms are those functors between the underlying posets that are left adjoints), take to be the partially ordered set of truth values, but this time as the opposite of the poset . For a sup-lattice , may be identified with the set of representable functors . The Chu condition then is that is representable for every representable . But this condition is equivalent ‘s being a left adjoint. Therefore the functor is full.
For other examples of concrete categories, the presence of enough elements in to detect the -structure of often requires some form of choice principle, such as the axiom of choice or ultrafilter theorem:
It follows that the functor is full.
Similar considerations apply to Boolean algebras, Stone Boolean algebras, algebraic lattices, and so on.
In all of these cases, the fullness of these embeddings entitles one to identify a topological space, a Boolean algebra, a vector space over , etc. with its corresponding Chu space, and the same consideration applies to the duals (opposites) of these categories.
Now many of these formal categorical duals are themselves concrete categories, as in the famous example of classical Stone duality between Boolean algebras and Stone spaces, i.e., compact Hausdorff totally disconnected topological spaces. In many such Stone duality situations, and certainly wherever Stone duality applies to the categories listed above, a contravariant equivalence between a concrete category and an algebraic category (i.e., where is monadic),
is effected by lifting the object of to a -algebra structure in (making an ambimorphic object, carrying - and -structures compatible with one another); equivalently, seeing as an algebra over the monad for which is monadic. For example, classical Stone duality is the case where is the category of Stone spaces, is the category of Boolean algebras, and the Boolean operations on are continuous with respect to its Stone space structure, making a Boolean algebra object in the category of Stone spaces. (For much more on this, see Johnstone’s classic treatise Stone Spaces, especially the chapter on general concrete dualities.)
The point is that in each of these situations, a Stone duality is a restriction of the more global duality on Chu spaces, in that the diagram
(where the vertical arrows are full embeddings as described above) commutes up to canonical isomorphism.
The same principle extends to other situations. For example, Pontryagin duality is fully embedded in the larger duality which obtains on , where is the category of abelian groups internal to a nice category of spaces. (Barr has also shown that Pontryagin duality is embedded in a sub--autonomous category of , and one might conceivably hope to find it in as well by analogy to the above appearance of algebras inside .)
Similarly, the 2-Chu construction, , exhibits dualities, such as Gabriel-Ulmer duality.
One of the simplest occurrences of Chu space constructions, and the one explored in Pratt 1999, leads to examples that although extremely simple have a well developed theory with connections to areas of logic and to formal concept analysis. This will be explored in a separate entry, Chu spaces, simple examples.
Recall from the above that is a -polycategory whenever is a co-subunary polycategory. This construction is functorial, and we claim that it defines a right adjoint to the forgetful functor from -polycategories to co-subunary polycategories.
To see this, consider first the -polycategory freely generated by one object. It has two objects and , and in addition to identity morphisms it has a dual pair and . Of these, all but the last are co-subunary. Thus, a morphism consists of two objects and (plus their identity morphisms) and a morphism — in other words, an object of .
Now consider the -polycategory freely generated by two objects and and a morphism . It contains two copies of generated by and , together with , its dual , and two other copies of it and . Of these all but the last are co-subunary, so a morphism is determined by two objects of together with three more morphisms (and some composition laws relating them to the duality morphisms). This yields the two morphisms and of a morphism in , along with their common composite .
Similarly, one can characterize all the morphisms in by mapping out of , where is the -polycategory freely generated by a -ary co--ary morphism.
As a special case of this universal property, if all the -polycategories are representable and the subunary polycategories are representable, closed, with a counit, and have pullbacks, we obtain an adjunction between a certain category of -autonomous categories and a certain category of closed symmetric monoidal categories with chosen objects. This is the way it was phrased in Pavlovic 97.
The construction originates with
Po-Hsiang Chu, Constructing -autonomous categories, appendix to: Michael Barr, -Autonomous Categories, Lecture Notes in Mathematics 752, Springer (1979) 103-138 [doi:10.1007/BFb0064579]
Michael Barr, -Autonomous categories and linear logic, Math. Structures Comp. Sci. 1 2 (1991) 159–178 [doi:10.1017/S0960129500001274, pdf, pdf]
Michael Barr, The Chu construction, Theory Appl. Categories 2 2 (1996) 17–35 [tac:2-02]
Further early discussion:
Michael Barr, Separability of tensor in Chu categories of vector spaces, Math. Structures Comp. Sci. 6 (1996) 213–217 [doi:10.1017/S0960129500000955, pdf, pdf]
Duško Pavlović, Chu I: cofree equivalences, dualities and -autonomous categories, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 7 1 (1997) 49-73 [doi:10.1017/S0960129596002046]
Michael Barr, The separated extensional Chu category Theory Appl. Categories 4 6 (1998) 127–137 [tac:4-06]
Vaughan Pratt, The second calculus of binary relations, Mathematical Foundations of Computer Science 1993. MFCS 1993, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 711, Springer (1993) [doi:10.1007/3-540-57182-5_9]
Vaughan Pratt, Chu Spaces (1999) [pdf, pdf, webpage]
Michael Barr, On duality of topological abelian groups, [pdf]
Vaughan Pratt, Linear process algebra, in: Distributed Computing and Internet Technology ICDCIT 2011, Lecture Notes in Computer Science 6536, Springer (2011) [doi:10.1007/978-3-642-19056-8_6, pdf]
(uses where is a 4-element set to model concurrency)
On the history of the notion:
Further resources:
Vaughan Pratt, Chu Spaces [webpage]
Algebras and Bialgebras via categories with distinguished objects [pdf]
See also:
Wikipedia, Chu space
Todd Trimble on the n-Cafe.
On categorifications and generalizations:
Mike Shulman, The 2-Chu Construction, (blog post)
Mike Shulman, The 2-Chu-Dialectica construction and the polycategory of multivariable adjunctions, 2018 arxiv
Last revised on October 28, 2023 at 06:51:35. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.