analysis (differential/integral calculus, functional analysis, topology)
metric space, normed vector space
open ball, open subset, neighbourhood
convergence, limit of a sequence
compactness, sequential compactness
continuous metric space valued function on compact metric space is uniformly continuous
…
…
higher geometry / derived geometry
Ingredients
Concepts
geometric little (∞,1)-toposes
geometric big (∞,1)-toposes
Constructions
Examples
derived smooth geometry
Theorems
physics, mathematical physics, philosophy of physics
theory (physics), model (physics)
experiment, measurement, computable physics
Axiomatizations
Tools
Structural phenomena
Types of quantum field thories
The concept of Euclidean space in analysis, topology, differential geometry and specifically Euclidean geometry, and physics is a fomalization in modern terms of the spaces studied in Euclid 300BC, equipped with the structures that Euclid recognised his spaces as having.
In the strict sense of the word, Euclidean space of dimension is, up to isometry, the metric space whose underlying set is the Cartesian space and whose distance function is given by the Euclidean norm:
In Euclid 300BC this is considered for ; and it is considered not in terms of coordinate functions as above, but via axioms of synthetic geometry.
This means that in a Euclidean space one may construct for instance the unit sphere around any point, or the shortest curve connecting any two points. These are the operations studied in (Euclid 300BC), see at Euclidean geometry.
Of course these operations may be considered in every (other) metric space, too, see at non-Euclidean geometry. Euclidean geometry is distinguished notably from elliptic geometry or hyperbolic geometry by the fact that it satisfies the parallel postulate.
In regarding (only) as a metric space, some extra structure still carried by is disregarded, such as its vector space structure, hence its affine space structure and its canonical inner product space structure. Sometimes “Euclidean space” is used to refer to with that further extra structure remembered, which might then be called Cartesian space.
Retaining the inner product on top of the metric space structure means that on top of distances one may also speak of angles in a Euclidean space.
Then of course carries also non-canonical inner product space structures, not corresponding to the Euclidean norm. Regarding as equipped with these one says that it is a pseudo-Euclidean space. These are now, again in the sense of Cartan geometry, the local model spaces for pseudo-Riemannian geometry.
Finally one could generalize and allow the dimension to be countably infinite, and regard separable Hilbert spaces as generalized Euclidean spaces.
Arguably, the spaces studied by Euclid were not really modelled on inner product spaces, as the distances were lengths, not real numbers (which, if non-negative, are ratios of lengths). So we should say that has an inner product valued in some oriented line (or rather, in ). Of course, Euclid did not use the inner product (which takes negative values) directly, but today we can recover it from what Euclid did discuss: lengths (valued in ) and angles (dimensionless).
Since the days of René Descartes, it is common to identify a Euclidean space with a Cartesian space, that is for the dimension. But Euclid's spaces had no coordinates; and in any case, what we do with them is still coordinate-independent.
Instead of working in the real numbers and -dimensional real vector spaces , one could instead work in a Archimedean ordered Artinian local -algebra and rank -modules . has infinitesimals, and so the -modules have infinitesimals as well. Nevertheless, it is still possible to define the Euclidean distance function on ; the only difference is that the distance function is a pseudometric rather than a metric here.
Since is an local ring, the quotient of by its ideal of non-invertible elements is itself, and the canonical function used in defining the quotient ring is the function which takes a number to its purely real component . Since is an ordered -algebra, there is a strictly monotone ring homomorphism .
The real numbers have lattice structure and . This means that has a distance function given by the function , defined as
as well as an absolute value given by the function , defined as
Since , the pseudometric and multiplicative seminorm are always non-negative. In addition, by definition, the pseudometric takes any two elements and whose difference is an infinitesimal to zero .
Since is an Euclidean field, it has a metric square root function . Every rank -module with basis thus has a Euclidean pseudometric defined by
for module elements and and scalars and for index , where
If is an ordered field, then this reduces down to the Euclidean metric defined above.
In constructive mathematics, the real numbers used to define Euclidean spaces are the Dedekind real numbers , as those are the only ones that are Dedekind complete, in the sense of not having any gaps in the dense linear order. The Dedekind real numbers are also the real numbers that are geometrically contractible: whose shape is homotopically contractible .
In predicative constructive mathematics, the Dedekind real numbers are defined relative to a universe , and thus there are many different such Dedekind real numbers that could be used to define Euclidean spaces, one for each . However, each set of Dedekind real numbers would be large relative to the sets in the universe .
If the predicative constructive foundations does not have universes, then there doesn’t exist any dense linear order that is actually Dedekind complete in the usual sense, and so the usual definition of Euclidean space does not work. Some mathematicians have proposed to use Sierpinski space , the initial -frame, for defining the real numbers, in place of the large set of all propositions in a universe , but the real numbers in that case are only -Dedekind complete, which is a weaker condition than being Dedekind complete. Furthermore, Lešnik showed that for any two -frames and that embed into such that , if is the -Dedekind completion of and is the -Dedekind completion of , then , so the -Dedekind real numbers are not complete.
Given two points and of a Euclidean space , their difference belongs to the vector space , where it has a norm
This real number (or properly, element of the line ) is the distance between and , or the length of the line segment . This distance function makes into an (-valued) metric space.
Given three points , with (so that ), we can form the ratio
which is a (dimensionless) real number. By the Cauchy–Schwartz inequality, this number lies between and , so it's the cosine of a unique angle measure between and radians. This is the measure of the angle . In a -dimensional Euclidean space, we can interpret as a signed angle (so taking values anywhere on the unit circle) if we fix an orientation of .
Conversely, knowing angles and lengths, we may recover the inner product on ;
and other inner products are recovered by linearity. (We must then use the axioms of Euclidean geometry to prove that this is well defined and actually an inner product.) It’s actually possible to recover the inner product and angles from lengths alone; this is discussed at Hilbert space.
Textbook accounts:
On the use of the Dedekind real numbers in constructive and predicative constructive mathematics, such as for Euclidean spaces:
Last revised on September 5, 2023 at 15:03:54. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.