natural deduction metalanguage, practical foundations
type theory (dependent, intensional, observational type theory, homotopy type theory)
computational trinitarianism =
propositions as types +programs as proofs +relation type theory/category theory
model category, model -category
Definitions
Morphisms
Universal constructions
Refinements
Producing new model structures
Presentation of -categories
Model structures
for -groupoids
on chain complexes/model structure on cosimplicial abelian groups
related by the Dold-Kan correspondence
for equivariant -groupoids
for rational -groupoids
for rational equivariant -groupoids
for -groupoids
for -groups
for -algebras
general -algebras
specific -algebras
for stable/spectrum objects
for -categories
for stable -categories
for -operads
for -categories
for -sheaves / -stacks
A cubical-type model category is a model category structure whose fibrations are defined by lifting against a generalized form of open box inclusions.
The term is not a precise technical one, but refers to model structures arising from a family of constructions, the first of which is due to Sattler (2017). These constructions are motivated by cubical type theory and can in particular be applied in certain categories of cubical sets.
The inputs to the construction are
a monomorphism in ;
with right adjoint on .
The map is intended as a classifier for the cofibrations, while the cylinder is used to define fibrations and acyclic cofibrations. The construction proceeds by building a cylindrical premodel category and then showing that it forms a model category.
The cofibrations, fibrations, and weak equivalences can be defined using just the data above, but further conditions on , , and are required to construct factorizations, to check that the premodel structure is cylindrical, and to prove 2-out-of-3 for weak equivalences.
The step from a premodel structure to a model structure is mediated by the following definition and proposition.
A premodel category has the fibration extension property if for every fibration and acyclic cofibration , there is a pullback square
in which is a fibration.
Let be a cylindrical premodel category in which all objects are cofibrant. If has the fibration extension property, then the class has the 2-out-of-3 property (i.e., is a model category).
The fibration extension property is then connected to the existence of fibrant classifiers for fibrations; see for example (Awodey et al. 2024, Section 3.6).
We first define the factorization system (AC,F).
A map is a cofibration when it can be written as a pullback of in .
A map in is an acyclic fibration when it has the right lifting property against all cofibrations.
Assume is a locally cartesian closed category and the cofibrations are closed under composition. Then the cofibrations and acyclic fibrations define a weak factorization system.
We need to show that
For the first point, regard as an object in the slice over . Then we have , where is the dependent sum along and is the dependent product along . When is the subobject classifier, this is the partial map classifier for . One may check that the map has the right lifting property against all cofibrations; this step uses the closure of cofibrations under composition.
By the Beck–Chevalley conditions, we have a pullback square
The map is a cofibration by construction. One may check that the composite is .
The second point follows from the retract argument after checking that the class of cofibrations is closed under retracts.
Variations on the construction differ in their definition of the fibrations and acyclic fibrations. We give the definition used in Sattler (2017).
A map is a fibration when it has the right lifting property against the pushout application for all and cofibrations . A map is a trivial cofibration when it has the left lifting property against the fibrations.
The above definition is appropriate when the cylinder functor admits connections in the sense of Gambino & Sattler (2017), which is related to the notion of connection on a cubical set. Other definitions are used in cases without connections; see for example (Awodey 2023).
Further assumptions on and the cylinder are needed to construct the (trivial cofibration, fibration) factorizations using the small object argument or algebraic small object argument; see for example Sections 3 and 7 of (Gambino & Sattler 2017) respectively. The algebraic route may be necessary to define the factorizations constructively.
For the (cofibration, trivial fibration) weak factorization system to be cylindrical, it is necessary to assume that the class of cofibrations is closed under pushout application .
For the premodel structure to be cylindrical, it then suffices to require that the cylinder functor admits a symmetry, meaning an isomorphism interacting with the cylinder structure in an appropriate way. See (Sattler 2017, Remark 4.3).
The proofs of the fibration extension property require first establishing that the (trivial cofibration, fibration) weak factorization system satisfies the Frobenius condition.
A proof for a setting with connections can be found in (Gambino & Sattler 2017). Proofs for settings without connections can be found in (Awodey 2023), (Hazratpour & Riehl 2024), and (Barton 2024).
A concrete application is to categories of cubical sets, i.e. presheaves over a category of cubes .
A simple and central choice for is the full subcategory of the category of posets on powers of . This is also the Lawvere theory of distributive lattices. The idempotent completion is the full subcategory of on finite lattices.
Other prominent examples are the Lawvere theories of de Morgan, Kleene, and boolean algebras.
For computational purposes we can take to be the smallest lattice of subobjects containing the cylinder endpoints (the faces of cubes). To get Cisinski model structures we can take . If we want the model to be effective, we also require that each proposition with is decidable. (This rules out taking .)
One may wonder whether these model structures are equivalent to the classical model structure on simplicial sets, i.e., whether they present classical homotopy theory.
This is not the case for cartesian cubes; see mailing-list. However, this model does form a Grothendieck (infinity,1)-topos, because it satisfies the Giraud axioms. For deMorgan cubical sets the geometric realization is not a Quillen equivalence (because of the reversal map); the counterexample is the unit interval quotient by the symmetry); see Sattler. Whether they are equivalent by another map is not yet excluded.
A modified model structure for cartesian cubes, the equivariant fibration model structure, does present classical homotopy theory (Awodey, Cavallo, Coquand, Riehl & Sattler (2024)). This model structure agrees with the test model structure on cartesian cubical sets.
The model structure for cartesian cubes with one connection also presents classical homotopy theory (Cavallo & Sattler (2022)). In this case an explicit equivariance condition on fibrations is not required (but is automatically satisfied). Again, the model structure agrees with the test model structure on the same category.
The question whether the geometric realization for the cubical sets based on distributive lattices is an equivalence is still open, cf. also Hackney and Rovelli and Streicher and Weinberger.
Sattler’s construction is in
and some elements appear in the earlier paper
The following two notes describe the construction, specialized to cubical sets, in more type-theoretic language.
Thierry Coquand, A model structure on some presheaf categories, pdf
Thierry Coquand, Some examples of complete Cisinski model structures, pdf
A refactoring of part of Sattler’s construction through the notion of “cylindrical premodel category” is described in Section 3 of
and in the unpublished note
Adaptations of the construction to cartesian cubical sets without connections can be found in
Steve Awodey, Cartesian cubical model categories (2023) [arXiv:2305.00893]
Evan Cavallo, Anders Mörtberg, Andrew W Swan, Unifying Cubical Models of Univalent Type Theory, 28th EACSL Annual Conference on Computer Science Logic (CSL 2020). [doi:10.4230/LIPIcs.CSL.2020.14]
Cubical-type model categories that present classical homotopy theory:
Evan Cavallo and Christian Sattler, Relative elegance and cartesian cubes with one connection (2022). [arXiv:2211.14801]
Steve Awodey, Evan Cavallo, Thierry Coquand, Emily Riehl, and Christian Sattler, The equivariant model structure on cartesian cubical sets (2024). [arXiv:2406.18497]
On equivalences with the model structure on simplicial sets:
Christian Sattler, Do cubical models of type theory also model homotopy types, lecture at Hausdorff Trimester Program: Types, Sets and Constructions, youtube
Philip Hackney and Martina Rovelli, Induced model structures for ∞-categories and ∞-groupoids, arXiv:2102.01104, Proc. Amer. Math. Soc., June 10, 2022
Thomas Streicher and Jonathan Weinberger, Simplicial sets inside cubical sets arXiv:1911.09594, Theory and Applications of Categories, Vol. 37, 2021, No. 10, pp 276–286
Proofs of the Frobenius condition:
Sina Hazratpour, Emily Riehl, A 2-categorical proof of Frobenius for fibrations defined from a generic point, Mathematical Structures in Computer Science 34, Special Issue 4 (2024) 258–280 [doi:10.1017/S0960129524000094,arXiv:2210.00078]
Reid Barton, A short proof of the Frobenius property for generic fibrations (2024) [arXiv:2402.04227]
Formalization of a version of the construction in the Coq proof assistant:
Last revised on January 1, 2025 at 01:45:37. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.