synthetic differential geometry
Introductions
from point-set topology to differentiable manifolds
geometry of physics: coordinate systems, smooth spaces, manifolds, smooth homotopy types, supergeometry
Differentials
Tangency
The magic algebraic facts
Theorems
Axiomatics
Models
differential equations, variational calculus
Chern-Weil theory, ∞-Chern-Weil theory
Cartan geometry (super, higher)
Der unendlich kleinste Theil des Raumes ist immer ein Raum, etwas, das Continuität hat, nicht aber ein blosser Punct, oder die Grenze zwischen bestimmten Stellen im Raume; (Fichte 1795, Grundriss, §4.IV)
In synthetic differential geometry one formulates differential geometry axiomatically in toposes – called smooth toposes – of generalized smooth spaces by assuming the explicit existence of infinitesimal neighbourhoods of points.
The main point of the axioms is to ensure that a well defined notion of the infinitesimal spaces exists in the topos, whose existence concretely and usefully formalizes the wide-spread but often vague intuition about the role of infinitesimals in differential geometry.
In particular, in such toposes there exists an infinitesimal space that behaves like the infinitesimal interval in such a way that for any space the tangent bundle of , is, again as an object of the topos, just the internal hom (using the notation of exponential objects in the cartesian closed category ). So a tangent vector in this context is literally an infinitesimal path in .
This way, in smooth toposes it is possible to give precise well-defined meaning to many of the familiar computations – wide-spread in particular in the physics literature – that compute with supposedly “infinitesimal” quantities.
As quoted by Anders Kock in his first book (p. 9), Sophus Lie – one of the founding fathers of differential geometry and, of course Lie theory – once said that he found his main theorems in Lie theory using “synthetic reasoning”, but had to write them up in non-synthetic style (see analytic versus synthetic) just due to lack of a formalized language:
“The reason why I have postponed for so long these investigations, which are basic to my other work in this field, is essentially the following: I found these theories originally by synthetic considerations. But I soon realized that, as expedient ( zweckmässig ) the synthetic method is for discovery, as difficult it is to give a clear exposition on synthetic investigations, which lead to deal with objects that till now have almost exclusively been considered analytically. After long vacillations, I have decided to use a half synthetic, half analytic form. I hope my work will serve to bring justification to the synthetic method besides the analytical one.” (Sophus Lie, Allgemeine Theorie der partiellen Differentialgleichungen erster Ordnung, Math. Ann. 9 (1876).)
Synthetic differential geometry provides this formalized language.
Another advocate of the use of infinitesimals in the late 19th century was the American philosopher Charles Sanders Peirce:
The illumination of the subject by a strict notation for the logic of relatives had shown me clearly and evidently that the idea of an infinitesimal involves no contradiction…As a mathematician, I prefer the method of infinitesimals to that of limits, as far easier and less infested with snares. Charles Sanders Peirce, The Law of Mind, The Monist 2 (1892)
According to Bell (1998, p.5):
Peirce was aware, even before Brouwer, that a faithful account of the truly continuous will involve jettisoning the law of excluded(.)
The axioms of synthetic differential geometry demand that the topos of smooth spaces is
in which in particular
infinitesimal spaces exist and
satisfy the Kock-Lawvere axiom.
Depending on applications one imposes further axioms, such as the
With that little bit of axiomatics alone, a large amount of differential geometry may be formulated. This has been carried through quite comprehensively by Anders Kock, see the reference below.
In his work he particularly makes use of the fact that as sophisticated as a smooth topos may be when explicitly constructed (see the section on models), being a topos means that one can reason inside it almost literally as in Set. Using this Kock’s work gives descriptions of synthetic differential geometry which are entirely intuitive and have no esoteric topos-theoretic flavor. All he needs is the assumption that the Kock-Lawvere axiom is satisfied for “numbers”. Here “numbers” is really to be interpreted in the topos, but if one just accepts that they satisfy the KL axiom, one may work with infinitesimals in this context in essentially precisely the naive way, with the topos theory in the background just ensuring that everything makes good sense.
Being axiomatic, reasoning in synthetic differential geometry applies in every model for the axioms, i.e. in every concrete choice of smooth topos .
Models of smooth toposes tend to be inspired by, but more general than, constructions familiar from algebraic geometry. In particular the old insight promoted by Grothendieck in his work, that nilpotent ideals in rings are formal duals of spaces with infinitesimal extension is typically used to model infinitesimal spaces in synthetic differential geometry.
See at synthetic differential geometry applied to algebraic geometry for more on this.
The main difference between models for smooth toposes and algebraic geometry from this perspective is that models for smooth topos tend to employ test spaces that are richer than plain formal duals to commutative rings or algebras, as in algebraic geometry: typical models for synthetic differential geometry use test spaces given by formal duals of generalized smooth algebras that remember “smooth structure” in the usual sense of differential geometry (and different from, though not entirely unrelated to, the notion of smooth scheme in algebraic geometry). This is in particular true for the well adapted models.
However, with a a sufficiently general perspective on higher geometry one finds that algebraic geometry and synthetic differential geometry are both special cases of a more general notion of theories of generalized spaces. For more on this see generalized scheme.
A topos modelling the axioms of synthetic differential geometry is called (well) adapted if the ordinary differential geometry of manifolds embeds into it, in particular if there is a full and faithful functor Diff from the category of ordinary smooth manifolds into .
A standard model for well adapted synthetic toposes is obtained in terms of sheaves on duals of “germ determined” -rings. This is described in great detail in the textbook Models for Smooth Infinitesimal Analysis.
The conception and discussion of these well adapted toposes goes back to Eduardo Dubuc, who studied them in a long series of articles. He asks people to refer to this topos as the Dubuc topos.
This theory of well-adapted models was later summarized and extended in the standard textbook
The notion of synthetic differential geometry extends to the context of supergeometry. See
The tangent bundle of an object in a smooth topos is just the exponential object . The unique inclusion induces a canonical projection . A section of that projection is a tangent vector field on . Its adjunct is a morphism that sends the unique point of to the identity .
A differential equation is an extension problem in a smooth topos along a morphism that includes an infinitesimal object into another object.
For instance the ordinary first order homogeneous differential equation that asks the derivative of a function along a vector field to be given by a specified map is given by a diagram of the form
where we have freely identified morphisms with their adjuncts. See differential equation for details.
A differential 1-form is a morphism that is “fiberwise linear”. One elegant way to say this is obtained by considering all higher differential forms at once:
for a sufficiently well behaved object in a smooth topos, there is the simplicial object which is the infinitesimal singular simplicial complex of . Taking functions on this produces the cosimplicial algebra . Its normalized Moore cochain complex is isomorphic to the de Rham dg-algebra of differential forms on :
This is discussed at
See at flow of a vector field.
The idea of axiomatizing differential geometry using ideas inspired by topos theory originates in
They were published as pp.1-28 in
The first model for the axioms presented there served to demonstrate that the theory is non-empty, but was hard to work with. Much of the later work was concerned with refining the model-building. For instance
These models are constructed in terms of sheaf toposes on the category of smooth loci, formal duals to C^∞-rings. See there for a detailed list of references.
Transcripts or notes of further talks by Bill Lawvere on the subject are
Bill Lawvere, Toposes of laws of motion , transcript of a talk in Montreal, Sept. 1997 (pdf)
(on the description of differential equations in terms of synthetic differential geometry)
Bill Lawvere, Outline of synthetic differential geometry , lectures in Buffalo (1998). (pdf)
Two articles that exhibit the link to continuum mechanics:
F. W. Lawvere, Toward the description in a smooth topos of the dynamically possible motions and deformations of a continuous body , Cah. Top. Géom. Diff. Cat. 21 no.4 (1980) pp.377-392. (pdf)
F. W. Lawvere, Categorical algebra for continuum microphysics , JPAA 175 (2002) pp.267-287.
See also
For the early French connection see:
André Weil, Théorie des points proches sur les variétés différentiables , Colloq. Top. et Géom. Diff., Strasbourg (1953) pp.111-117.
Jean Penon, De l’infinitésimal au local (Thèse de Doctorat d’État) Diagrammes S13 (1985), pp.1-191. (pdf)
Discussion in differential cohesion is in
Discussion in differentially cohesive homotopy type theory is in
Felix Wellen, Formalizing Cartan Geometry in Modal Homotopy Type Theory, 2017
David Jaz Myers, Orbifolds as microlinear types in synthetic differential cohesive homotopy type theory [arXiv:2205.15887]
A nice elementary introduction which emphasizes calculations and the application as engineering mathematics can be found in
The textbooks
Anders Kock, Synthetic Differential Geometry, Cambridge University Press (1981, 2006) [pdf, doi:10.1017/CBO9780511550812]
Anders Kock, Synthetic geometry of manifolds, Cambridge Tracts in Mathematics 180 (2010) [doi:10.1017/CBO9780511691690, pdf]
develop the theory of differential geometry using the axioms of synthetic differential geometry. The main goal in these books is to demonstrate how these axioms lead to a very elegant, very intuitive and very comprehensive conception of differential geometry. Accordingly, concrete models (whose explicit description is typically much more evolved than the nice axiomatics that holds once they have been constructed) play a minor role in these books.
Somewhat complementary to that, the book
focuses on concrete constructions of well-adapted models using the technology of generalized smooth algebras (-rings).
Another textbook is
Introductory survey includes
Anders Kock, Synthetic differential geometry - new methods for old spaces, talk at New Spaces for Mathematics and Physics, IHP Paris (2015) [video recording]
Anders Kock, New methods for old spaces: synthetic differential geometry [arxiv/1610.00286]
Introductory expositions of basic ideas of synthetic differential geometry are
Mike Shulman, Chicago Pizza-Seminar: Synthetic Differential Geometry (pdf)
John Lane Bell, An invitation to smooth infinitesimal analysis (pdf)
R. P. Kostecki, Differential Geometry in Toposes, ms. University of Warsaw (2009) pdf
Last revised on October 25, 2024 at 20:05:10. See the history of this page for a list of all contributions to it.